What and Why of Virtue Ethics ?

What and Why of Virtue Ethics ?

Key Terms

  • Ethics
  • Classical Virtues
  • Virtue Ethics
  • Normative Ethics
  • Meta Ethics
  • Kantian Ethics
  • Aristotle
  • Utilitarianism
    • John Stuart Mill
    • Jeremy Bentham
  • Consequentialism
  • Deontological Ethics
    • Immanuel Kant
  • Teleological Ethics
  • Act based Ethics
  • Person/Agent Based Ethics
  • Personality Traits
  • Character
  • Dispositions
  • Eudaimonistic Virtue Ethics
    • Nicomachean Ethics (Aristotle)
  • Sentimentalist Virtue Ethics
    • Michael Slote
  • Pluralistic Virtue Ethics
  • Plato
  • David Hume
  • Friedrich Nietzsche
  • Martin Heidegger
  • Confucian Ethics
  • Hinduism Ethics
  • Buddhist Ethics
  • Self, Culture, Nature
  • Aesthetics, Ethics, Logic
  • Truth, Beauty, Goodness
  • Phenomenology, Normative Science, Metaphysics
  • Varieties of Goodness
  • Forms of Ethics
  • Bio Ethics
  • Business Ethics
  • Applied Ethics
  • Narrative Ethics
  • Environmental Ethics

Key Scholars

  • G. E. M. Anscombe
  • Alasdair MacIntyre
  • Philippa Foot
  • Rosalind Hursthouse
  • Michael Slote
  • Christine Swanton
  • Julia Annas
  • Philip J Ivanhoe
  • May Sim
  • Robert C. Roberts
  • David Carr
  • Liezl van Zyl
  • Martha Nussbaum

Virtue Ethics

Source: THE ROUTLEDGE COMPANION TO VIRTUE ETHICS

Source: THE ROUTLEDGE COMPANION TO VIRTUE ETHICS

Source: THE ROUTLEDGE COMPANION TO VIRTUE ETHICS

R.B. Louden, in Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics (Second Edition), 2012

Abstract

Virtue ethics holds that judgments about the inner lives of individuals (their traits, motives, dispositions, and character) are of primary importance, and that judgments about the rightness or wrongness of acts and/or the consequences of acts are secondary. One major criticism levied against virtue ethics is that its strong agent perspective prevents it from giving sufficiently specific advice about how to act in problematic situations. In this article, the development and structure of contemporary virtue ethics is presented, the challenge posed by the application problem is analyzed, and responses to it by applied virtue ethicists are assessed.

Virtue Ethics

C. Swanton, in International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences, 2001

Virtue ethics is a species of normative ethical theory generally seen as opposed to both Kantian ethics and Consequentialism. In its modern incarnations, it has been largely inspired by the eudaimonistic tradition of the ancient Greeks, and in particular Aristotle. However, we can expect further developments in virtue ethics which are inspired by other sources, such as Nietzsche and Hume. Virtue ethics is characterized by the centrality of character in normative ethical theory, where norms of excellence of character provide norms for both the good life in general and acting well and rightly. In virtue ethical traditions, norms of excellence of character are rich, and involve being well disposed in regard to reason, feelings, desires, motives, emotions, as well as action. Hence, the importance of the expression of fine inner states in virtue ethics. Problems for virtue ethics include the foundations of virtue, the universality of virtue, the relation between character and issues in applied ethics such as role obligations and right action generally, demands for codifiability and determinacy, and ‘character skepticism’ suggested by situationist psychology.

J. Sim, in Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics (Second Edition), 2012

Virtue Ethics

Within a virtue ethics approach, the emphasis is not on what one does but on the kind of person one is in terms of certain morally desirable character traits, such as compassion, benevolence, sensitivity, discretion, honesty, selflessness, and courage. The importance of such virtues can be underlined in two ways. First, it can be argued that character traits such as compassion and discretion are necessary in order for a person to recognize the moral demands of a particular situation; for example, it is only through possessing a measure of discretion that one will recognize a situation in which confidentiality is called for. Second, having identified the moral dimension in a situation, these same character traits may provide the necessary impetus or motivation to act: feelings of compassion not only allow one to identify a situation in which there is a moral demand to act to relieve another’s distress but also propel one to do so. In the process, virtues may enable a more sensitive and judicious application of the principles espoused by deontology or of the process of evaluating outcomes proposed by consequentialism. The notion of ‘caring’ that is central to health professionals’ practice has a clear resonance with virtue ethics.

Ethics

Peter J. Smith, John J. Hardt, in Developmental-Behavioral Pediatrics (Fourth Edition), 2009

Virtue Ethics

The central tenant of virtue ethics holds that the moral life is best promoted by attending to the moral agent herself or himself. Whereas deontologic ethics identifies and follows duties or obligations and utilitarian ethics attempts to maximize the good for the greatest number, virtue ethics seeks the moral formation of persons rather than the valuation of actions by paying attention to human virtue, friendship, moral wisdom, and discernment. As noted before, virtue ethics has deep roots in the classical world, and its philosophical origins are found in the Hippocratic Collection. Virtue ethics emphasizes the dynamic nature of ethical decisions, recognizing that individuals both shape and are shaped by what they choose to do in any given situation. Whereas virtue ethics flourished in the classical, philosophical world (Aquinas, 1920), its influence waned during the enlightenment. Virtue ethics has more recently experienced a revival in the 20th century in the work of moral philosopher Alasdair MacIntyre (1981) and others who have creatively recovered the work of their predecessors.

Critics of virtue ethics argue that it, like deontology and utilitarianism, cannot function within a morally plural society because of the lack of agreement on what virtues are actually worthy of promotion. Who decides what constitutes the good life and the good person among our ongoing disagreements about morality and value? Furthermore, the person-centered nature of this ethical system, insofar as it focuses on the moral agent rather than on obligations or principles, makes its content difficult to translate into codes, regulations, policies, or laws (Jonsen and Toulmin, 1988).

Deontology, Consequentialism, and Virtue Ethics

Source: Varieties of Virtue Ethics

Theory versus exploration in virtue ethics

Until sometime in the 1980s philosophers of ethics tended to think that the major alternatives in ethical theory were deontology and utilitarianism. Deontology is the view that some principle of obligation — Kant’s categorical imperative is the dominant contender — is the foundation of morality. Actions gain their moral worth by being generated from this foundation, and the virtuous person is one who is properly sensitive to the foundational principle (has “respect for the moral law”). Utilitarianism is the view that the goodness of actions derives not from their generating principle, but from the quality of their consequences. A classic example is J. S. Mill’s view that actions’ goodness comes from their fostering the general happiness or correcting unhappiness. Each of these theories offers its preferred basis of morality as the single ultimate and exclusive basis of moral goodness and rightness (which is not to deny that some thinkers offer “mixed” or “impure” theories that admit both bases on an equal footing, thus turning two monisms into a dualism, so to speak).

Sometime in the 1970s some philosophers got the bright idea of proposing a third alternative ethical theory, which they called “virtue ethics.” It was to have the same formal structure as the two classic modern theories, but be more plausible. So the basic idea was that virtue, not a principle of obligation or good outcomes and states of affairs, would be the foundation of ethical distinctions. Michael Slote well represents this proposal:

An agent-based approach to virtue ethics treats the moral or ethical status of acts as entirely derivative from independent and fundamental aretaic (as opposed to deontic) ethical characterizations of motives, character traits, or individuals… (2001, p. 5; italics added).

Eduardo Mendieta, in Encyclopedia of Violence, Peace, & Conflict (Second Edition), 2008

Deontology and the Pursuit of Moral Life

Virtue ethics, like Confucian ethics another form of virtue ethics, has as a fundamental assumption that humans are not born moral, but instead are socialized into morality. In both cases, the socialization entails acquiring certain social habits and living in accordance with communally sanctioned or proscribed mores and manners. These morals, in other words, do not travel well. What may be a virtue in one community may be a vice in another. Most importantly, how do we decide whether a virtue is in fact a moral excellence? The pursuit of virtue, in other words, does not produced morality, but the pursuit of morality leads us to virtue. It is in response to these doubts that Immanuel Kant developed his absolutist, deontological, and cognitivistic ethics. Kant begins with a Socratic question: “Is the pious loved by the gods because it’s pious? Or is it pious because it’s loved?” (Euthyphro 10a). According to Kant, and Socrates as well, we cannot judge something moral just because we deem it so, or have been told so. Nor can we derive morality from examples, role models, or paragons of morality, for in labeling them as such, we already operate with an inchoate notion of the moral. Kant argues that we must suspend all appeal to history, folklore, and religion in order to reflect on what we take to be truly moral. In order to do this Kant investigates the a priori assumptions of all moral action. He engages in what he calls a transcendental investigation, that is, he seeks to uncover the conditions of possibility without which morality would not make any sense. According to Kant, there are two indispensable presuppositions of morality: an absolutely free will and a rational nature. Morality is possible at all because humans are metaphysically (absolutely and not contingently) free and they have poor reason. Duty draws out for us this rational and free dimension of morality. A moral act, according to Kant, is one that is done without coercion, or without the fear of retaliation or some punishment. A moral act is one that is done for its own sake, or else it is a not a moral act but a contingent action aimed at achieving some specific end. When we act from duty, we act out of respect for the moral law. The moral worth of a moral act, therefore, is determined not by something external to it, but by the maxim (or principle that determines the will) according to which it is executed. If the moral worth of an act would be determined by something external, then the will would not be free and we would act out of inclination, desire, passion, or moral weakness. Duty thus reflects precisely how the moral is that which is universally necessary and commanded by the power of our reason. To act from duty is to act in accordance with reason and the determination of the free will. There is no other force or power that determines morality than the power of self-legislated duty. Duty in fact aims at what Kant called ‘categorical imperatives,’ which in contrast to hypothetical imperatives, are what must be done. While hypothetical imperatives are conditional, contingent, and aim at short-lived or narrow ends in such a way that the ends necessitate certain means, categorical imperatives are unconditional and unqualified and apply to all human conditions, and aim not at contingent and short-lived aims but at the very dignity of the human being. According to Kant in his Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, there is only one categorical imperative, which he formulates in this way: “Act only in accordance with that maxim through which you can at the same time will that it become a universal law.” Moral acts are only those that can be universalized. According to Kant this principle of the universability of moral law can be expressed in three other formulas: act in such a way that you treat the humanity of others as well as your own humanity, always as an end and never as a means; act in such a away that you always assume every ‘rational being’ to be a will that ‘legislates universal law,’ and act in such a way that you take yourself, and all other rational beings, to be members of a ‘kingdom of ends.’ The categorical imperative in its three versions essentially argues that morality is the expression of the moral autonomy of rational beings that legislate upon themselves laws that command their utmost respect. Morality, in other words, both expresses the dignity of the human being and commands its utmost reverence and respect. Notwithstanding its seeming rigor and absolutism, Kantianism is parsimonious and abstemious; it neither presuppose reference to specific cultural contexts and customs, nor does it offer a set of rules. The categorical imperative merely makes implicit that which we take to be indispensable and inalienable to morality; but it also offers us a North Star. As Kant noted in the conclusion to his Critique of Practical Reason: “Two things fill the mind with ever new and increasing admiration and reverence, the more often and more steadily one reflects on them: the starry heavens above and the moral law within me.” Like the lawfulness of the cosmos, which renders it both mysterious and awe-inspiring, the self-legislated lawfulness of morality, renders us admirable and sublime.

Source: Ethics of Physiotherapy

Varieties of Virtue Ethics

Source: THE ROUTLEDGE COMPANION TO VIRTUE ETHICS

  • Plato and the Ethics of Virtue
  • Aristotle’s Virtue Ethics
  • The Stoics Theory of Virtue
  • Hindu Virtue Ethics
  • Why Confucius’s Ethics is a Virtue Ethics
  • Mencius’s Virtue Ethics
  • Virue in Buddhist Ethical Traditions
  • Respect for Differences
  • Xunzi and Virtue Ethics
  • Consecrated Virtue
  • Thomas Aquinas
  • David Hume
  • Nietzsche and the Virtues
  • Eudaimonistic Virtue Ethics
  • Sentimentalist Virtue Ethics
  • Pluralistic Virue Ethics
  • Contemporary Christian Virtue Ethics
  • Contemporary Confucianism
  • Virtue Epistemology and Virue Ethics
  • Feminist Virtue Ethics
  • Agape and Virtue Ethics
  • Kant and Virtue Ethics
  • The Consequentialist Critique of Virtue Ethics
  • Virtue Ethics and Right Action
  • Virtue Ethics and Egoism
  • Models of Virtue
  • The Situationist Critique
  • Testing the Empathy-Altruism Hypothesis against Egoistic Alternatives
  • Care Ethics and Virtue Ethics
  • Roles and Virtues
  • Environmental Virtue Ethics
  • World Virtue Ethics
  • Virtue Ethics And Moral Education
  • Virtue Ethics As Political Philosophy
  • Law And Virtue
  • Virtue Ethics And Medicine
  • Business Ethics From A Virtue-Theoretic Perspective

Source: Virtue Ethics: A Contemporary Introduction

Source: A virtue ethics perspective on bioethics

Key features of virtue ethics

The most fundamental claim made by virtue ethics as a theory of right action is that reference to character and virtue are essential in the justification of right action (see Hursthouse 1999, pp. 28-31). A virtue-ethics-criterion right action can be stated initially in broad terms as holding that an action is right if and only if it is what an agent with a virtuous character would do in the circumstances (see Hursthouse, 1991, p. 225). That is, a right action is one that a virtuous person would do in the circumstances, and what makes the action right is that it is what a person with a virtuous character would do here.

An important qualification was subsequently made to this initial statement of a virtue-ethics-criterion of right action. In responding to concerns that even virtuous agents might occasionally act wrongly when they act contrary to their virtuous characters, Rosalind Hursthouse stipulated that the virtuous exemplar in the above criterion of right action must be understood to be acting in character (Hursthouse 1999, p. 28). Other variants of virtue ethics have recently been developed that specify the link between virtue and right action somewhat differently from that mentioned above. For example, Christine Swanton (2003) advocates what she calls a ‘target-centered’ approach, whereby virtuous actions are those that hit the target – realize the proper goal – of the virtue relevant to the context, and right actions are those that are overall virtuous in the circumstances in which the actual agent finds themselves (pp. 228-40). Nevertheless, the primacy given to character in both of these versions helps to distinguish virtue ethics from standard forms of Kantianism, Utilitarianism, and Consequentialism, whereby actions are justified according to rules or outcomes.

Of course, if virtue ethics is to guide and justify actions, this criterion clearly needs to be supplemented by an account of which character-traits count as virtues. (Similarly, a rule-utilitarian criterion of right action needs to be supplemented by an account of which universally adopted rules maximize utility.) Nevertheless, the above formulations already highlight a key difference between virtue ethics and standard Kantian and Utilitarian approaches, whereby the rightness of an act is determined by whether the act is in accordance with certain rules, or by whether it maximizes expected utility, respectively. For neither of those approaches, as standardly defined, make reference to character essential to the justification of right action. For example, Utilitarians like Henry Sidgwick (1981, p. 227) saw virtues such as generosity, gratitude, and courage as instrumentally valuable, insofar as they help to bring about the pleasure and happiness of sentient beings, or a life of ‘desirable consciousness’ (especially in circumstances where we have insufficient time to deliberate).

It is important to clarify that doing what the virtuous agent would do involves not merely the performance of certain acts, but requires acting from certain dispositions and (in many cases) certain motives. For example, acting as someone with the virtue of benevolence would act involves not only providing assistance to another person but also includes having and acting from a genuine concern for their well-being, and a disposition to have and act from that concern in particular kinds of situations. As Aristotle (1980, VI, 13, 1144b26-9) put it, “It is not merely the state in accordance with the right rule, but the state that implies the presence of the right rule, that is virtue”. Acting as the virtuous agent would act typically involves acting from certain motives – though one can act justly from a variety of motives, so long as one acts from a disposition that incorporates an appropriate sense of justice. Every virtue can be thought to embody a regulative ideal, involving the internalization of a certain conception of excellence such that one is able to adjust one’s motivation and conduct so that they conform to that standard. Indeed, Julia Annas (2011) has argued that the nature of virtues must be understood by grasping how virtues are acquired, in the way that skills like piano-playing are acquired. That is, virtues should be viewed as comparable to skills “that exhibit the practical intelligence of the skilled craftsperson or athlete” (Annas 2011, p. 169). Annas argues that “part of the attraction of an ethics of virtue has always been the point that virtue is familiar and recognizable by all, so it would still be a damaging result if virtue is hopelessly unattainable by all but a few”(p. 173; see also Russell 2009).

A key difference between virtue ethics and standard Utilitarian and Kantian ethical theories is the close connection typically drawn by virtue ethics between motive and rightness. Most forms of Utilitarianism and Kantianism hold that, generally speaking, one can act rightly, whatever one’s motivation – so long as one maximizes expected utility or acts in accordance with duty, one has done the right thing, whether one’s motives were praiseworthy, reprehensible, or neutral. However, as we have seen, virtue ethics typically holds that acting rightly (in most situations) requires acting from a particular sort of motivation, since this is part of what is involved in doing what a virtuous person would do in the circumstances. Indeed, Michael Slote (2001, 2007) has developed an ‘agent-based’ virtue ethics, whereby an action is right if and only if it is done from a virtuous motive, such as benevolence. Acting from the virtuous motive of benevolence, in Slote’s view, is not simply acting to help another from a warm-hearted feeling towards them, but involves seeking via an active capacity for empathy to understand their plight, and monitoring one’s action to see that it is actually helping.

Distinguishing virtue ethics more fully from contemporary versions of Kantian and Utilitarian approaches requires filling in the details about which character-traits count as virtues (see Oakley 1996). So, just as Kantians and Utilitarians need to detail their general criteria of rightness by specifying which rules we are to act in accordance with, or what expected utility consists of, virtue ethicists must likewise provide details about what the virtues are. For virtue ethics to be capable of guiding action, the criterion of right action outlined above needs to be completed with an account of the virtues. The distinctiveness of virtue ethics compared to other theories is brought out more fully when we consider the ways in which advocates of the approach ground the normative conceptions in the character of the virtuous agent.

Many virtue ethicists hold the Aristotelian view that virtues are character traits that we need to live humanly flourishing lives. In this view, developed principally by Foot (1978, 2001) and Hursthouse (1987, 1999), benevolence and justice are virtues because they are part of an interlocking web of intrinsic goods – which includes friendship, integrity and knowledge – without which we cannot have eudaimonia. According to Aristotle, the characteristic activity of human beings is the exercise of our rational capacity, and only by living virtuously is our rational capacity to guide our lives expressed in an excellent way. Construing virtues as character traits that humans need to lourish, Hursthouse argues that what makes a character trait a virtue in humans is that it serves well the following four ‘naturalistic’ ends: individual survival, individual characteristic enjoyment and freedom from pain, the good functioning of the social group, and the continuance of the species (1999, pp. 200-1, 208, 248). Aristotle argues that each virtue can be understood as involving hitting the mean between two vices – for example, the virtue of courage is the mean between the vices of cowardice and rashness. However, Aristotle realizes that telling us to aim at a mean between excess and defect is vague: “if a man had only this knowledge he would be none the wiser – eg, we should not know what sort of medicines to apply to our body if some were to say ‘all those which the medical art prescribes, and which agree with the practice of one who possesses the art’ ” (1980, VI, 1, 1138b29-33). So Aristotle proceeds to develop his account of ethical judgment as practical wisdom (phronesis), as a way of explaining how virtues can guide actions.

A different approach to grounding the virtues, pioneered by Michael Slote (1992), rejects the eudaimonist idea of Aristotle that virtues are found by considering what humans need in order to lourish, and instead derives virtues from our commonsense views about what character traits we typically find admirable – as exemplified in the lives of figures such as Albert Einstein and Mother Teresa – whether or not those traits help an individual to flourish. Swanton (2003) also rejects Aristotelian eudaimonism, and argues that virtues are dispositions to respond to morally significant features of objects in an excellent way, whether or not such dispositions are good for the person who has them. For example, Swanton (2203, pp. 82-3) argues that a great artist’s creative drive can be a virtue, even if this drive leads the artist to suffer bipolar disorder – such an artist’s creative drive need not bring flourishing, but Swanton argues it is nevertheless an excellent way of responding to value, and can certainly result in a life that is justifiably regarded as successful in some sense.

My Related Posts

The Great Chain of Being

Indra’s Net: On Interconnectedness

Mind, Consciousness and Quantum Entanglement

Consciousness of Cosmos: A Fractal, Recursive, Holographic Universe

Cosmic Mirror Theory

Fractal Geometry and Hindu Temple Architecture

Geometry of Consciousness

Truth, Beauty, and Goodness

Truth, Beauty, and Goodness: Integral Theory of Ken Wilber

The Aesthetics of Charles Sanders Peirce

The Good, the True, and the Beautiful

Aesthetics and Ethics

Aesthetics and Ethics: At the Intersection

Phenomenology and Symbolic Interactionism

Meta Integral Theories: Integral Theory, Critical Realism, and Complex Thought

On Classical Virtues

On Holons and Holarchy

Human Rights and Human Development

Third and Higher Order Cybernetics

Arts and Moral Philosophy

Psychology of Happiness: Value of Storytelling and Narrative Plays

Key Sources of Research

Ethics of Physiotherapy

J. Sim,

in Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics (Second Edition), 2012

https://www.sciencedirect.com/topics/psychology/virtue-ethic

“Introduction” ,


van Hooft, Stan , 

in The Handbook of Virtue Ethics 

ed. Stan van Hooft , Nafsika Athanassoulis , Jason Kawall , Justin Oakley , Nicole Saunders and Liezl Van Zyl 

(Abingdon: Routledge, 27 Nov 2013 ), accessed 01 Oct 2022 , Routledge Handbooks Online.

https://www.routledgehandbooks.com/doi/10.4324/9781315729053.ch1#S1

Virtue Ethics: A Contemporary Introduction

By Liezl van Zyl

Routledge, 2019

On Virtue Ethics

1st Edition

by Rosalind Hursthouse

ISBN-13: 978-0198238188

ISBN-10: 0198238185

Intelligent Virtue

1st Edition

by Julia Annas (Author)

ISBN-13: 978-0199228775

ISBN-10: 0199228779

The Cambridge Companion to Virtue Ethics

(Cambridge Companions to Philosophy) 0th Edition

by Daniel C. Russell (Editor)

ISBN-13: 978-0521171748
ISBN-10: 0521171741

The Routledge Companion to Virtue Ethics

(Routledge Philosophy Companions) 1st Edition

by Lorraine Besser-Jones (Editor), Michael Slote (Editor)

ISBN-13: 978-1138478220
ISBN-10: 1138478229

Virtue Ethics

(Oxford Readings in Philosophy) 1st Edition

by Roger Crisp (Editor), Michael Slote (Editor)

ISBN-13: 978-0198751885
ISBN-10: 0198751885

Natural Goodness

1st Edition

by Philippa Foot (Author)

ISBN-13: 978-0199265473

ISBN-10: 019926547X

Kant: Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

(Cambridge Texts in the History of Philosophy) 2nd Edition

by Mary Gregor (Translator), Jens Timmermann (Translator), Christine M. Korsgaard (Introduction)

ISBN-13: 978-1107401068
ISBN-10: 1107401062

Nicomachean Ethics

Third Edition, third edition

by Aristotle (Author), Terence Irwin (Translator)

ISBN-13: 978-1624668159
ISBN-10: 1624668151

Utilitarianism

Second Edition

by John Stuart Mill (Author), George Sher (Editor)

ISBN-13: 978-0872206052
ISBN-10: 087220605X

Virtue Ethics

Science Direct Page

https://www.sciencedirect.com/topics/psychology/virtue-ethic

Virtue Ethics: A Critical Reader

Daniel Statman (ed.)
Georgetown University Press (1997)
ISBN: 9780878402205

ISBN: 9780878402212 (0878402217)

http://press.georgetown.edu/book/georgetown/virtue-ethics

https://philpapers.org/rec/STAVE

Varieties of Virtue Ethics

edited by David Carr, James Arthur, Kristján Kristjánsson

Virtue Ethics and Consequentialism in Early Chinese Philosophy

By Bryan van Norden

The Virtue Ethics of Hume and Nietzsche

By Christine Swanton


Virtue Ethics and the Chinese Confucian Tradition 

Chapter

in Book Virtue Ethics and Confucianism

By PHILIP J. IVANHOE

Edition 1st Edition, First Published 2013, Imprint Routledge

eBook ISBN 9780203522653

https://www.taylorfrancis.com/chapters/edit/10.4324/9780203522653-11/virtue-ethics-chinese-confucian-tradition-philip-ivanhoe

Varieties of Virtue Ethics

Robert C. Roberts
Distinguished Professor of Ethics Emeritus, Baylor University

From James Arthur, David Carr, and Kristján Kristjánsson, eds., Varieties of Virtue Ethics (Palgrave Macmillan, 2017)

THE ETHICS OF THE NODE VERSUS THE ETHICS OF THE DYAD? RECONCILING VIRTUE ETHICS AND CONTRACTUALISM*

Pursey P. M. A. R. Heugens
Muel Kaptein
J. (Hans) van Oosterhout

ORGANIZATION STUDIES 27(3): 391-411.

After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory

Third Edition Paperback – Download: Adobe Reader, March 6, 2007

First Ed – 1981

by Alasdair MacIntyre (Author)

A Short History of Ethics: A History of Moral Philosophy from the Homeric Age to the Twentieth Century,

Second Edition Paperback – Download: Adobe Reader, January 15, 1998

by Alasdair MacIntyre (Author)

Virtue Ethics

(2018) 

Rhetoric Review, 37:4, 321-392, 

DOI: 10.1080/07350198.2018.1497882

https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/full/10.1080/07350198.2018.1497882

A Problem Based Reading of Nussbaum’s Virtue Ethics

by John C. Brady

Epoche Magazine

Issue #16 September 2018

https://epochemagazine.org/16/a-problem-based-reading-of-nussbaums-virtue-ethics/

Being Virtuous and Doing the Right Thing.

Annas, J. (2013).

In R. Shafer-Landau, Ethical Theory: An Anthology (2nd ed., pp. 676–686). West Sussex: Wiley-Blackwell.

Normative Virtue Ethics.

Hursthouse, R. (2013).

In R. Shafer-Landau, Ethical Theory: An Anthology (2nd ed., pp. 645–652). West Sussex: Wiley-Blackwell.

Virtue Ethics: A Misleading Category. 

Nussbaum, M. (1999).

The Journal Of Ethics3(3), 163–201. doi: 10.1023/a:1009829301765

Non-Relative Virtues: An Aristotelian Approach.

Nussbaum, M. (2013).

In R. Shafer-Landau, Ethical Theory: An Anthology (2nd ed., pp. 630–644). West Sussex: Wiley-Blackwell.

Varieties of Virtue Ethics in Philosophy, Social Science and Theology,

Oriel College, Oxford, January 8th–10th, 2015

The third annual conference of the Jubilee Centre for Character and Virtues, University of Birmingham. UK

https://www.jubileecentre.ac.uk/502/conferences/varieties-of-virtue-ethics

Which Variety of Vitue Ethics?

Julia Annas

This is an unpublished conference paper for the 3rd Annual Jubilee Centre for Character and Virtues conference at Oriel College, Oxford University, Thursday 8th – Saturday 10th January 2015.

Why Confucius’s Ethics is a Virtue Ethics

May Sim

This is an unpublished conference paper for the 3rd Annual Jubilee Centre for Character and Virtues conference at Oriel College, Oxford University, Thursday 8th – Saturday 10th January 2015.

Normative Virtue Ethics

Rosalind Hursthouse

Click to access hursthouse_-_normative_virtue_ethics.pdf

A virtue ethics perspective on bioethics

Una perspectiva de la ética de la virtud en bioética

Justin Oakley

Centre for Human Bioethics, Monash University, Melbourne, Australia

Received 10 March 2015; accepted 27 March 2015

BIOETHICS UPdate 1 (2015) 41-53

A Virtue Ethical Account of Right Action

Christine Swanton

Ethics

Volume 112, Number 1 October 2001

https://doi.org/10.1086/322742

https://www.journals.uchicago.edu/doi/pdf/10.1086/322742

The Virtue of “Virtue Ethics” in Business and Business Education

https://www.semanticscholar.org/paper/The-Virtue-of-“Virtue-Ethics”-in-Business-and-Wittmer-O’Brien/b140b4cd37d9264e33425851cb21cbacd1063289

Modern Moral Philosophy

https://www.semanticscholar.org/paper/Modern-Moral-Philosophy-Anscombe/41dd2aaa779faf3d40599a6711cabd07284d7775

Toward a Synthesis of Confucianism and Aristotelianism

Bryan W Van Norden

Chapter in Book Virtue Ethics and Confucianism
Edited by Stephen C. Angle and Michael Slote

2013

https://www.academia.edu/12762325/Toward_a_Synthesis_of_Confucianism_and_Aristotelianism

BWVN Virtue Ethics and Confucianism

Bryan W Van Norden

Chapter 5 in Book

https://www.academia.edu/12762328/BWVN_Virtue_Ethics_and_Confucianism


Why Virtue Ethics? Action and motivation in virtue ethics

Norah Woodcock*

McGill University

Aporia Vol. 19 No. 1

Virtue Ethics

First published Fri Jul 18, 2003; substantive revision Thu Dec 8, 2016

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy

https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ethics-virtue/

Virtue Ethics

Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Virtue Ethics

Wikipedia

https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Virtue_ethics

AN INTRODUCTION TO WESTERN ETHICAL THOUGHT: ARISTOTLE, KANT, UTILITARIANISM

Heather Wilburn, Ph.D.

Virtue ethics of clinical research

Letter to the Editor

María Pérez‐Piñar1, Luis Ayerbe1,2

1The Westborough Road Health Centre, Westcliff‐on‐Sea, Essex, SS0 9PT, 2Centre for Primary Care and Public Health, Queen Mary University of London, London, United Kingdom

Dr. Luis Ayerbe, Centre for Primary Care and Public Health, Queen Mary University of London, Yvonne Carter Building, 58, Turner Street, London E1 2AB, United Kingdom. E‐mail: l.garcia‐morzon@qmul.ac.uk

The Handbook of Virtue Ethics

Stan van Hooft

2014

https://www.routledge.com/The-Handbook-of-Virtue-Ethics/Hooft/p/book/9781844656394

VIRTUE ETHICS

Michael Slote

Virtue Ethics

Speaker: David Massey

Indian Hill Schools

“Virtue Ethics” 

Julia Annas

The Oxford Handbook of Ethical Theory, edited by David Copp and published in 2007.

A virtue ethics approach to moral dilemmas in medicine

P Gardiner

J Med Ethics 2003;29:297–302

Virtue Ethics

Klement

Univ of Mass, MA

Virtue Ethics

Publisher: Wiley-Blackwell

Copyright Date:  2002

Author (Faculty Member):  Stephen Darwall

Virtue Ethics collects, for the first time, the main classical sources and the central contemporary expressions of virtue ethics approach to normative ethical theory. Includes classic essays by Aristotle, Francis Hutcheson and David Hume, and recent reactions to this work by philosophers including Philippa Foot, John McDowell, Alasdair MacIntyre, Annette Baier, Rosalind Hursthouse, and Michael Slote. With an introduction by Stephen Darwall as well as a contemporary discussion on character and virtue by Gary Watson.

https://philosophy.yale.edu/publications/virtue-ethics

Virtue Ethics

CHAPTER 12

THE ELEMENTS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY

James Rachels and Stuart Rachels

Click to access james_rachels_and_stuart_rachels_virtue_ethics.pdf

Ethical Theories

The Arthur W. Page Center Public Relations Ethics

Penn State

https://pagecentertraining.psu.edu/public-relations-ethics/introduction-to-public-relations-ethics/lesson-1/ethical-theories/

Consumer Moral Leadership

January 2010

Sue L.T. Mcgregor
Mount Saint Vincent University

https://www.researchgate.net/publication/267220449_Consumer_Moral_Leadership

Code Biology, Bio-Semiotics, and Relational Biology

Code Biology, Bio-Semiotics, and Relational Biology

Key Terms

  • Biosemiotics
  • Anticipatory Systems
  • Code biology
  • Relational biology
  • C.S. Peirce
  • T. Sebeok
  • Jesper Hoffmeyer
  • Marcello Barbieri
  • Robert Rosen
  • Rom Harré
  • F Schelling
  • Habits
  • Pratibha
  • Innate Ability
  • Archetypes
  • Talent
  • Character
  • Virtues
  • Caste System
  • Astrology
  • Invariance
  • Regularities
  • Periodicities
  • Sapta Rishis
  • Evolution
  • Development
  • Biology
  • Codes
  • Meaning
  • Culture
  • Nature

Archetypes and Code Biology

Source: Archetypes and code biology

As a clinical psychologist, I observe stereotyped formulas of behavior in action every day in the consulting room, despite differences in age, race, or culture; they present themselves as codified rules or typical modes of behavior in archetypical situations. Such circumstances coincide with what C.G. Jung defended: the existence of archetypes stored in an inherited/phylogenetic repository, which he called the collective unconscious – somewhat similar to the notion of an ethogram, as shown by ethology. Psychologists can use a perspective to facilitate understanding the phenomenon: the code biology perspective (Barbieri 2014). This approach can help us recognize how these phenomenological events have an ontological reality based not only on the existence of organic information but also on the existence of organic meaning.

We are not a tabula rasa (Wilson 2000): despite the explosive diversification of the brain and the emergence of conscience and intentionality, we observe the conservation of basic instincts and emotions (Ekman 2004Damasio 2010) not only in humans but in all mammals and other living beings; we refer to the neural activity on which the discrimination behavior is based, i.e., the neural codes. The conservation of these fundamental set-of-rules or conventions suggests that one or more neural codes have been highly conserved and serves as an interpretive basis for what happens to the living being who owns them (Barbieri 2003). Thus, archetypes’ phenomenological reality can be understood not as something metaphorical but as an ontological (phylogenetic) fact (Goodwyn 2019).

Furthermore, epigenetic regulation theories present the possibility that the biomolecular process incorporates elements of the context where it takes place; something fundamental to understand our concept – the archetype presents itself as the mnesic remnant of the behavioral history of individuals who preceded us on the evolutionary scale. In short: brains are optimized for processing ethologically relevant sensory signals (Clemens et al., 2015).

From the perspective of the corporeal mind (Searle 2002), in this paper, we will show the parallels between code biology and the concept of the archetype, as Jung defended it and as it appears in clinical practice.

Source: Code Biology 3: the study of all Codes of Life

Editorial
Overview of the third special issue in code biology

  1. Introduction
    This third special issue in Code Biology is a collection of highly different papers and their differences have two main causes. The first, the most obvious, is that Code Biology is the study of all codes that exist in living systems and the diversity of the papers is a direct consequence of the diversity of the codes. The second source of diversity is the existence of different theories. More precisely, the original theory that gave origin to Code Biology has been followed by a number of extended theories that now coexist with the original one. In Code Biology, in other words, there is pluralism but there has also been a beginning, and it is important to be clear about this starting point. The original theory of Code Biology is characterized by ideas that make it different from four major theoretical frameworks:
    1. [1] The original theory of Code Biology is different from the Modern Synthesis for two reasons. The first is the idea that evolution took place by natural selection and by natural conventions and these mechanisms are fundamentally different because natural selection is based on copying and natural conventions are based on coding. The second is the idea that the cell is not a biological computer made of genotype and phenotype but a trinity of genotype, phenotype and ribotype, where the ribotype is the ribo nucleoprotein system of the cell that functions as the codemaker of the genetic code (Barbieri 1981, 1985, 2003).
    2. [2] The original theory of Code Biology maintains that the fundamental process of life is not autopoiesis but codepoiesis (Barbieri 2012). Autopoiesis requires biological specificity and specificity comes from the genetic code, so the ancestral systems that came before that code could not have been autopoietic systems. Those ancestral systems, on the other hand, were engaged in the evolution of the genetic code and were therefore codepoietic systems. Autopoiesis, furthermore, is most evident in bacteria and bacteria have not increased their complexity and have not evolved new codes for billions of years after their appearance on Earth. It was the eukaryotes that became increasingly complex and that evolved new codes, which suggests a deep link between codes and complexity, and in particular between the origin of new codes and the origin of the great novelties of macroevolution (Barbieri 2015, 2016, 2017, 2020). Codepoiesis, on the other hand, is necessarily implemented by mechanisms, and according to the original theory of Code Biology the major mechanism that fuelled the evolution of the genetic code was the process of ambiguity reduction (Barbieri 2019a).
    3. [3] The original theory of Code Biology is different from Biosemiotics because it claims that the Peircean processes of interpretation and abduction take place in the brain but not in the cell (Barbieri 2014,2018).
    4. [4] The original theory of Code Biology is different from the Relational Biology of Robert Rosen because it assumes that the process of anticipation takes place in the brain but not in the cell (Barbieri 2019b).
  2. There are, in conclusion, four key ideas in the original theory of Code Biology:
    1. [a] Evolution took place by natural selection and by natural conventions.
      [b] The cell is a trinity of genotype, phenotype and ribotype.
      [c] The fundamental process of life is codepoiesis, not autopoiesis.
      [d] Ambiguity reduction was the major evolutionary mechanism of the genetic code.
  3. The extended theories of Code Biology differ from the original theory either because they introduce new concepts or because they reformulate some of the original concepts.
    1. [1] The first extended theory appeared when Stefan Kühn and Jan-Hendrik Hofmeyr (2014) proposed an extended definition of code, a definition where signs and meanings can be not only molecules but also biological processes. More precisely, Kühn and Hofmeyr showed that the histone code is a mapping where the signs are the marks produced on histones by acetylation or methylation processes and their meanings are the activation or the repression of particular genes.
    2. [2] A second extended theory of Code Biology has been proposed in this issue by Julie Heng and Henry Heng with the idea that the adaptors of a biological code can be “information flows”. More precisely, Heng and Heng point out that in addition to the codes that produce the components of a system there are also codes that organize those components into a working whole. The code that is used to make bricks, for example, is different from the code that is used to construct a building from those bricks. The genetic code is a code that makes bricks, i.e., proteins, but in order to arrange proteins into a living system we need an architectural code that Heng and Heng call “karyotype code”.
    3. [3] A third extended theory is presented in this issue by Omar Paredes and colleagues on the grounds that the original theory of Code Biology “raises the illusion that information has only an upward direction … whereas the current overview of cellular dynamics … illustrates that information flows freely upward and downward”. In order to overcome this limitation, the authors propose “a novel category of organic codes, the metacode”, which is defined as “an informational structure that handles the continuum of the information flow in biological systems”.

The extended theories, in short, are a reality and their existence is a testimony that there is genuine pluralism in Code Biology. The goal of this special issue, on the other hand, is to give a bird’s-eye view of the present status of Code Biology and to this purpose it has been divided into four parts, each of which is going to be illustrated in the rest of this editorial with brief presentations of its papers

My Related Posts

Semiotics, Bio-Semiotics and Cyber Semiotics

What is Code Biology?

Autocatalysis, Autopoiesis and Relational Biology

Systems Biology: Biological Networks, Network Motifs, Switches and Oscillators

Hierarchy Theory in Biology, Ecology and Evolution

System Archetypes: Stories that Repeat

On Classical Virtues

Key Sources of Research

Code Biology, Peircean Biosemiotics, and Rosen’s Relational Biology

Marcello Barbieri

Biological Theory 14 (1):21-29 (2019)

https://philpapers.org/rec/BARCBP-2

Code biology: A bird’s-eye view

Author(s): Marcello Barbieri

Gatherings in Biosemiotics XX.
(Tartu Semiotics Library 20.) Tartu: University of Tartu Press.

Issue Year: 2020 Issue No: 20 Page Range: 72-91

Lacková, Ľudmila; Rodríguez H., Claudio J.; Kull, Kalevi (eds.) 2020. 

BIOSEMIOSIS AND CAUSATION:
DEFENDING BIOSEMIOTICS THROUGH ROSEN’S THEORETICAL BIOLOGY
OR
INTEGRATING BIOSEMIOTICS AND ANTICIPATORY SYSTEMS THEORY1

Arran Gare

Cosmos and History: The Journal of Natural and Social Philosophy, vol. 15, no. 1, 2019

https://philarchive.org/archive/GARBAC-4

A Critique of Barbieri’s Code Biology Through Rosen’s Relational Biology: Reconciling Barbieri’s Biosemiotics with Peircean Biosemiotics. 

Vega, F.

Biol Theory 13, 261–279 (2018).

https://doi.org/10.1007/s13752-018-0302-1

https://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/s13752-018-0302-1

Click to access VEGA_CUESTA_Federico_Tesis.pdf

An Integrated Account of Rosen’s Relational Biology and Peirce’s Semiosis. Part I: Components and Signs, Final Cause and Interpretation

Federico Vega

Biosemiotics (2021) 14:697–716

https://doi.org/10.1007/s12304-021-09441-z

https://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/s12304-021-09441-z

Click to access VEGA_CUESTA_Federico_Tesis.pdf

An Integrated Account of Rosen’s Relational Biology and Peirce’s Semiosis. Part II: Analysis of Protein Synthesis. 

Vega, F.

Biosemiotics 14, 717–741 (2021).

https://doi.org/10.1007/s12304-021-09438-8

https://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/s12304-021-09438-8

Click to access VEGA_CUESTA_Federico_Tesis.pdf

Peircean habits and the life of symbols

Thirty-fifth Meeting of the Semiotic Society of America October 21-24, 2010, Louisville, Kentucky

Eliseo Fernández
Linda Hall Library of Science and Technology

fernande@lindahall.org

BIOSEMIOTICS AND SELF-REFERENCE FROM PEIRCE TO ROSEN

Eliseo Fernández

Linda Hall Library of Science and Technology5109 Cherry St.Kansas City, MO 64110, USA

fernande@lindahall.org

Eighth Annual International Gatherings in Biosemiotics

University of the Aegean, Syros, Greece, June 23-28, 2008

Functional Information: Towards Synthesis of Biosemiotics and Cybernetics

Alexei A. Sharov

National Institute on Aging, 251 Bayview Boulevard, Baltimore, MD 21224, USA Alexei A. Sharov: sharoval@mail.nih.gov

Entropy (Basel). 2010 Apr 27; 12(5): 1050–1070. 

doi: 10.3390/e12051050

https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC3285384/

Codes: Necessary, but not sufficient for meaning-making.

Kull K. (2020)

Constructivist Foundations 15(2): 137–139.

https://constructivist.info/15/2/137

Organic Codes: A Unifying Concept for Life.

de Farias, S.T., Prosdocimi, F. & Caponi, G.

Acta Biotheor 69, 769–782 (2021).

https://doi.org/10.1007/s10441-021-09422-2

https://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/s10441-021-09422-2

A critique of Barbieri’s code Biology

Alexander V. Kravchenko
Baikal State University

https://www.researchgate.net/publication/344896397_A_critique_of_Barbieri%27s_code_Biology

Origin and evolution of the genetic code: the universal enigma

Eugene V. Koonin* and Artem S. Novozhilov
National Center for Biotechnology Information, National Library of Medicine, National Institutes of Health, Bethesda, MD 20894

IUBMB Life. 2009 February ; 61(2): 99–111. doi:10.1002/iub.146.

https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC3293468/

Code biology and the problem of emergence

Arran Gare 

Bio Systems 2021 Oct; 208:104487.

doi: 10.1016/j.biosystems.2021.104487.

https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/34273444/

https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/abs/pii/S0303264721001349?via%3Dihub

Archetypes and code biology

J.C.Major

International Academy of Analytical Psychology, Portugal

Biosystems
Volume 208, October 2021, 104501

https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/abs/pii/S0303264721001489

The major evolutionary transitions and codes of life

Adam Kun

Bio Systems 210 2021

https://doi.org/10.1016/j.biosystems.2021.104548

Code Biology 3: the study of all Codes of Life

Edited by Marcello Barbieri

Last update 22 September 2021

3rd Special Issue in Code Biology

Bio Systems December 2021

https://doi.org/10.1016/j.biosystems.2021.104553

https://www.sciencedirect.com/journal/biosystems/special-issue/10S60V7SHC6

Code Biology 2: the study of all Codes of Life

Edited by Marcello Barbieri, Jan-Hendrik Hofmeyr

Last update 30 June 2021

Bio Systems Feb 2018

2nd Special Issue on Code Biology

https://doi.org/10.1016/j.biosystems.2019.104050

https://www.sciencedirect.com/journal/biosystems/special-issue/10Q35Z29R86

The first Special Issue on code biology – A bird’s-eye view

Jan-Hendrik S Hofmeyr 

Bio Systems 2018 Feb; 164:11-15.

doi: 10.1016/j.biosystems.2017.12.007.

Epub 2017 Dec 16.

https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/29258888/

https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/abs/pii/S030326471730463X?via%3Dihub

https://www.sciencedirect.com/journal/biosystems/vol/164/suppl/C

GATHERINGS IN BIOSEMIOTICS

Edited by
Silver Rattasepp Tyler Bennett

TARTU SEMIOTICS LIBRARY 11

2012

Series editors: Kalevi Kull Silvi Salupere Peeter Torop

Department of Semiotics

University of Tartu
Jakobi St. 2

Tartu 51014, Estonia

Gatherings in Biosemiotics XX

Edited by
Ľudmila Lacková Claudio J. Rodríguez H. Kalevi Kull

2020

TARTU SEMIOTICS LIBRARY 20

http://www.flfi.ut.ee/en/department-semiotics/tartu-semiotics-library

Tartu: University of Tartu Press.

Semiotic Agency: Science Beyond Mechanism

By Alexei Sharov, Morten Tønnessen

A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO PEIRCE IN BIOSEMIOTICS

CLAUDIO J. RODR ́IGUEZ H. CLAUDIOJRODRIGUEZH@GMAIL.COM

Chapter One
Peirce in contemporary semiotics

Paul Cobley

In: The Bloomsbury Companion to Contemporary Peircean Semiotics. Jappy, Tony, ed. Bloomsbury Companions . Bloomsbury Academic, London, pp. 31-72.

2019

doi:10.5040/9781350076143.ch-001

https://eprints.mdx.ac.uk/25834/1/Chapter%201%20%20Peirce%20in%20contemporary%20semiotics%20pre-print%20.docx

Consciousness, Mind and Spirit. 

Gare, A. (2019).

Cosmos and History: The Journal of Natural and Social Philosophy15(2), 236–264.

Retrieved from https://mail.cosmosandhistory.org/index.php/journal/article/view/833

FROM KANT TO SCHELLING TO PROCESS METAPHYSICS: ON THE WAY TO ECOLOGICAL CIVILIZATION

Arran Gare

Cosmos and History: The Journal of Natural and Social Philosophy, vol. 7, no. 2, 2011

https://philarchive.org/archive/GARFKT-6

Toward an Ecological Civilization: The Science, Ethics, and Politics of Eco-Poiesis*

Arran Gare

PROCESS STUDIES 39.1 (2010)

Beyond Descartes and Newton: Recovering Life and Humanity

Stuart A. Kauffman and Arran Gare

Stu modification 3/11/15 Arran modification 5/17/15

Published in Progress in Biophysics and Molecular Biology, 119(3), 2017: 219-244.

Language and the Self-Reference Paradox

Julio Michael Stern

Cybernetics And Human Knowing. Vol. 14, no. 4, pp.71-92

Overcoming the Newtonian paradigm: The unfinished project of theoretical biology from a Schellingian perspective

Arran Gare*
Philosophy, Faculty of Life and Social Sciences, Swinburne University, Melbourne, Australia

Published in Progress in Biophysics and Molecular Biology, 113, (2013): 5-24.