Axiology of Thinking

Axiology of Thinking

Source: Axiology and Logic

Axiology is the philosophical study of value, which originally meant the worth of something. It includes the studies of moral values, aesthetic values, as well as political and social values. Logic, on the other hand, is a philosophical study of arguments and the methods and principles of right reasoning.

Is Logic part of Aesthetics?

Key Terms

  • Axiology
  • Philosophy
  • Ethics
  • Aesthetics
  • Moral Values
  • Virtues
  • Virtue Ethics
  • Values
  • Culture
  • Normative Culture
  • Goodness
  • Three types of Goodness
  • Charles Sanders Peirce
  • A N Whitehead
  • Pragmatism
  • Process Philosophy
  • Robert C. Neville
  • Axiology of Thinking
  • Beauty in Experience
  • Aesthetics of Experience
  • Emotions
  • Positive Emotions
  • Negative Emotions
  • Wellness
  • Society
  • Big Tent
  • Mahayana Buddhism
  • Hinduism
  • Big Boat
  • Evolution of Culture
  • Design Thinking
  • Justice and Injustice
  • Laws
  • Human Development
  • Human Capabilities
  • Limits and Boundaries
  • Acceptable and Unacceptable
  • Rules and Norms
  • Pratha
  • Sanskriti
  • Bhav and Ras
  • Harmony and Dissonance
  • Monks and Brahmins
  • Guru and Pandit
  • Priests
  • Monks and Society
  • Communication
  • Access to Ideas
  • Access to Knowledge

Monks who are busy in meditation and contemplation on reality depend on alms and charity provided by the society. Monks would not survive in a society which is not charitable, just, and respectful towards Monks and their role in the society.

Culture matters as much as Monks’ philosophy.

Source: Reconstruction of Thinking

Source: Recovery of the Measure: Interpretation and Nature

Source: Normative Cultures

Source: Normative Cultures

Source: Axiology and Logic

Lesson Overview
We have said earlier that philosophy deals with the most basic issues faced by human beings. Axiology is the philosophical study of value, which originally meant the worth of something. It includes the studies of moral values, aesthetic values, as well as political and social values. Logic, on the other hand, is a philosophical study of arguments and the methods and principles of right reasoning. In this lesson, we will discuss Axiology and Logic as the other two major fields of philosophy.

4.1 Axiology

Activity # 1: – Dear learners, what do you think is Axiology? List any question that you might think is an axiological question. Show your question to student(s) beside you, and discuss about your questions together.

Axiology is the study or theory of value. The term Axiology stems from two Greek words – “Axios”, meaning “value, worth”, and “logos”, meaning “reason/ theory/ symbol / science/study of”. Hence, Axiology is the philosophical study of value, which originally meant the worth of something. Axiology asks the philosophical questions of values that deal with notions of what a person or a society regards as good or preferable, such as:

  • What is a value?
  • Where do values come from?
  • How do we justify our values?
  • How do we know what is valuable?
  • What is the relationship between values and knowledge?
  • What kinds of values exist?
  • Can it be demonstrated that one value is better than another?
  • Who benefits from values?
  • Etc.

Axiology deals with the above and related issues of value in three areas, namely Ethics, Aesthetics, and Social/Political Philosophy.

I. Ethics

Activity # 2: – Dear learners, how do you define ethics? What ethical rules, principles, and standards do you know and follow, and why? Discuss about it with the student(s) beside you.

Ethics, which is also known as Moral Philosophy, is a science that deals with the philosophical study of moral principles, values, codes, and rules, which may be used as standards for determining what kind of human conduct/action is said to be good or bad, right or wrong. Ethics has three main branches: meta-ethics, normative ethics, and applied ethics. Ethics raises various questions including:

  • What is good/bad?
  • What is right/wrong?
  • Is it the Right Principle or the Good End that makes human action/conduct moral?
  • Is an action right because of its good end, or it is good because of its right principle?
  • Are moral principles universal, objective, and unconditional, or relative, subjective and conditional?
  • What is the ultimate foundation of moral principles? The supernatural God? Human reason? Mutual social contract? Social custom?
  • Does God exist? If so, is He Benevolent and Omnipotent?
  • If God is Benevolent, why He creates evil things? If God does not create evil things, then, there must be another creator who is responsible to creation of the evil things? But, if it is so, how can God be an Omnipotent creator?
  • Why we honor and obey moral rules? For the sake of our own individual benefits?, or for the sake of others?, or just for the sake of fulfilling our infallible duty?

Ethics, or ethical studies, can be grouped into three broad categories: Normative ethics, Meta-ethics, and Applied Ethics.

Normative Ethics refers to the ethical studies that attempt to study and determine precisely the moral rules, principles, standards and goals by which human beings might evaluate and judge the moral values of their conducts, actions and decisions. It is the reasoned search for principles of human conduct, including a critical study of the major theories about which things are good, which acts are right, and which acts are blameworthy. Consequentialism or Teleological Ethics, Deontological Ethics, and Virtue Ethics are the major examples of normative ethical studies.

Meta-ethics is the highly technical philosophical discipline that deals with investigation of the meaning of ethical terms, including a critical study of how ethical statements can be verified. It is more concerned with the meanings of such ethical terms as good or bad and right or wrong than with what we think is good or bad and right or wrong. Moral Intuitionism, Moral Emotivism, Moral Prescriptivism, Moral Nihilism, and Ethical Relativism are the main examples of meta-ethical studies.

Applied Ethics is a normative ethics that attempts to explain, justify, apply moral rules, principles, standards, and positions to specific moral problems, such as capital punishment, euthanasia, abortion, adultery, animal right, and so on. This area of normative ethics is termed applied because the ethicist applies or uses general ethical princes in an attempt to resolve specific moral problems.

II. Aesthetics

Activity # 3: – Dear learners, how do you define and understand aesthetics? What Discuss about it with the student(s) beside you.

Aesthetics is the theory of beauty. It studies about the particular value of our artistic and aesthetic experiences. It deals with beauty, art, enjoyment, sensory/emotional values, perception, and matters of taste and sentiment.
The following are typical Aesthetic questions:

  • What is art?
  • What is beauty?
  • What is the relation between art and beauty?
  • What is the connection between art, beauty, and truth?
  • Can there be any objective standard by which we may judge the beauty of artistic works, or beauty is subjective?
  • What is artistic creativity and how does it differ from scientific creativity?
  • Why works of art are valuable?
  • Can artistic works communicate? If so, what do they communicate?
  • Does art have any moral value, and obligations or constraints?
  • Are there standards of quality in Art?

III. Social/Political Philosophy

Activity # 4: – Dear learners, how do you define politics and society? What political and social rules, principles, and standards do you know and follow, and why? Discuss about it with the student(s) beside you.

Social/Political Philosophy studies about of the value judgments operating in a civil society, be it social or political.
The following questions are some of the major Social/Political Philosophy primarily deal with:

  • What form of government is best?
  • What economic system is best?
  • What is justice/injustice?
  • What makes an action/judgment just/unjust?
  • What is society?
  • Does society exist? If it does, how does it come to existence?
  • How are civil society and government come to exist?
  • Are we obligated to obey all laws of the State?
  • What is the purpose of government?

4.2 Logic

Activity # 5: – Dear learners, how do you define and understand logic? Discuss about it with student(s) beside you.

Logic is the study or theory of principles of right reasoning. It deals with formulating the right principles of reasoning; and developing scientific methods of evaluating the validity and soundness of arguments. The following are among the various questions raised by Logic:

  • What is an argument; What does it mean to argue?
  • What makes an argument valid or invalid
  • What is a sound argument?
  • What relation do premise and conclusion have in argument?
  • How can we formulate and evaluate an argument?
  • What is a fallacy?; What makes an argument fallacious?

My Related Posts

The Aesthetics of Charles Sanders Peirce

Aesthetics and Ethics

Aesthetics and Ethics: At the Intersection

On Aesthetics

On Beauty

What and Why of Virtue Ethics ?

On Classical Virtues

Key Sources of Research

Reconstruction of Thinking

(AXIOLOGY OF THINKING SERIES)

Unabridged. Edition
by Robert Cummings Neville (Author)

The Renaissance development of science fulfilled the ancient ideal of integrating quantitative and qualitative thinking, but failed to recognize valuational thinking and thus deprived moral, aesthetic, and political thought of cognitive status. The task of this book is to reconstruct the concept of thinking in order to exhibit valuation, not reason, as the foundation for thinking and to integrate valuational with quantitative and qualitative modes. Part I explains the broad thesis, interpreting the problem of the foundations for thinking and providing a general theory of value. Part II explains the role of valuation at the imaginative level of thinking with discussions of synthesis, perception, form, and art. The method of reconstruction requires a cosmology that is generated in successive waves.

Recovery of the Measure: Interpretation and Nature

(Axiology of Thinking, Vol. 2) (Axiology of Thinking; 2)

Paperback – August 15, 1989
by Robert Cummings Neville (Author)

“The world is as we interpret it.” Arguing that this assumption is a major and pervasive error, Neville demonstrates that the world is the measure of our interpretations. Distinguishing two traditions of hermeneutics, the continental tradition focusing on the interpretation of texts and the American tradition on the interpretation of nature; Neville argues that, since interpretation itself is part of the natural world, a philosophical vision of nature must be restored to currency in order to provide an interpretive theory of the world that can be a measure of interpretation. The natural world must be construed richly enough to be inclusive of human intention and purpose. By taking the discussion of hermeneutics from the context of textuality and placing it within that of nature, Recovery of the Measure provides a non-modernist and non-postmodernist theory of interpretation.

The first four chapters and the last four constitute a hermeneutical theory addressing contemporary problems of interpretation situated in the context of the philosophy of nature. The middle chapters provide a compact philosophy of nature dealing with being, identity, value, space, time, motion, and causation.

“Neville’s systematic, self-conscious employment of Peirce’s theory of the sign as a means of locating the project of a philosophy of nature within the context of contemporary hermeneutical thinking is extremely fortunate. By so doing Neville has opened his thought to a ready assessment by continental thinkers and has placed himself near the center of contemporary philosophic debate. Because of its timeliness, the brilliance of its arguments, and the profundity of its conclusions, there is good reason to believe that this work will shortly become the focus of genuine and widespread discussion. With the publication of this latest installment of his Axiology of Thinking, Neville emerges as one of the strongest voices in American philosophy.” — David L. Hall

Normative Cultures

(Axiology of Thinking Series) (Axiology of Thinking, Vol 3)

Paperback – August 17, 1995
by Robert Cummings Neville (Author)

Robert Cummings Neville is Professor of Philosophy, Religion, and Theology at Boston University where he is also Dean of the School of Theology. He is past president of the American Academy of Religion, the Metaphysical Society of America, and the International Society for Chinese Philosophy. Neville has also written Behind the Masks of God: An Essay Toward Comparative Theology; New Essays in Metaphysics; The Puritan Smile: A Look Toward Moral Reflection; and The Tao and the Daimon, all published by SUNY Press.

“The subject of Neville’s Normative Cultures is the rebirth of philosophy as a ‘worldly’ enterprise. There is no topic more significant than this one for the philosopher truly responsive to the present demands of his discipline.” ― David L. Hall, The University of Texas

The Tao and the Daimon: Segments of a Religious Inquiry

Hardcover – June 30, 1983
by Robert Cummings Neville (Author)

The Tao and the Daimon examines a central theme in religious studies: the question of the authority and authenticity of traditional religious faith and practice (tao) in light of the challenge from the spirit of critical reason (Socrates’ daimon). From a non-judgmental, historical standpoint, it develops the dialectical relation between religion and rational inquiry. Neville employs a philosophical system to set a task for reflection, making it possible to see how Eastern and Western religious traditions differ, overlap, contradict, and reinforce one another. The central chapters are detailed studies of theologically interesting elements in Christianity, Buddhism, taoism, and Neoconfucianism.

How can one judge of the higher truths of another religion without having practiced it? Can the tao and the daimon, after all, be reconciled purely in the conceptual realm of speculative philosophy? Neville recognizes the very real differences between conceptualizing and practicing and the very real differences in understanding that can result. At the same time, he transcends the problem by identifying (and exemplifying in his own work) speculative philosophy as a tao in itself, “a new locus of religious significance, our own scholarly interpretation, new creations of the holy out of practiced scholarly piety toward the old.”

Boston Confucianism: Portable Tradition in the Late-Modern World (Suny Series in Chinese Philosophy and Culture)

Paperback – September 22, 2000
by Robert Cummings Neville (Author), Tu Weiming (Foreword)

Ultimates: Philosophical Theology, Volume One

Paperback – July 2, 2014
by Robert Cummings Neville (Author)

God the Creator: On the Transcendence and Presence of God 

Paperback – February 13, 1992 

by  Robert Cummings Neville  (Author)

The Center of Neville’s Vision: An Elegant Axiology. 

Frankenberry, N. (2019).

American Journal of Theology & Philosophy 40(3), 82-89.  https://www.muse.jhu.edu/article/751987.

‘The Status of Time in Robert C. Neville’s Axiology of Thinking’, 

Slater, Gary, 

C. S. Peirce and the Nested Continua Model of Religious Interpretation, Oxford Theology and Religion Monographs (Oxford, 2015; online edn, Oxford Academic, 17 Dec. 2015), https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198753230.003.0006

accessed 19 May 2023.

https://academic.oup.com/book/8811/chapter-abstract/154991481?redirectedFrom=fulltext

‘Introduction: What is the Nested Continua Model?’, 

Slater, Gary, 

C. S. Peirce and the Nested Continua Model of Religious Interpretation, Oxford Theology and Religion Monographs (Oxford, 2015; online edn, Oxford Academic, 17 Dec. 2015), https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198753230.003.0001, accessed 19 May 2023.

Metaphysics of Goodness: Harmony and Form, Beauty and Art, Obligation and …

By Robert Cummings Neville

Self, Nature, and Cultural Values

Md. Munir Hossain TALUKDER
Department of Philosophy, National University of Singapore 3 Arts Link, Singapore 117570, Singapore mdmhtalukder@gmail.com

Cultura. International Journal of Philosophy of Culture and Axiology · January 2010 

DOI: 10.5840/cultura2010726

Axiology and Logic

Axiology and Logic

What and Why of Virtue Ethics ?

What and Why of Virtue Ethics ?

Key Terms

  • Ethics
  • Classical Virtues
  • Virtue Ethics
  • Normative Ethics
  • Meta Ethics
  • Kantian Ethics
  • Aristotle
  • Utilitarianism
    • John Stuart Mill
    • Jeremy Bentham
  • Consequentialism
  • Deontological Ethics
    • Immanuel Kant
  • Teleological Ethics
  • Act based Ethics
  • Person/Agent Based Ethics
  • Personality Traits
  • Character
  • Dispositions
  • Eudaimonistic Virtue Ethics
    • Nicomachean Ethics (Aristotle)
  • Sentimentalist Virtue Ethics
    • Michael Slote
  • Pluralistic Virtue Ethics
  • Plato
  • David Hume
  • Friedrich Nietzsche
  • Martin Heidegger
  • Confucian Ethics
  • Hinduism Ethics
  • Buddhist Ethics
  • Self, Culture, Nature
  • Aesthetics, Ethics, Logic
  • Truth, Beauty, Goodness
  • Phenomenology, Normative Science, Metaphysics
  • Varieties of Goodness
  • Forms of Ethics
  • Bio Ethics
  • Business Ethics
  • Applied Ethics
  • Narrative Ethics
  • Environmental Ethics

Key Scholars

  • G. E. M. Anscombe
  • Alasdair MacIntyre
  • Philippa Foot
  • Rosalind Hursthouse
  • Michael Slote
  • Christine Swanton
  • Julia Annas
  • Philip J Ivanhoe
  • May Sim
  • Robert C. Roberts
  • David Carr
  • Liezl van Zyl
  • Martha Nussbaum

Virtue Ethics

Source: THE ROUTLEDGE COMPANION TO VIRTUE ETHICS

Source: THE ROUTLEDGE COMPANION TO VIRTUE ETHICS

Source: THE ROUTLEDGE COMPANION TO VIRTUE ETHICS

R.B. Louden, in Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics (Second Edition), 2012

Abstract

Virtue ethics holds that judgments about the inner lives of individuals (their traits, motives, dispositions, and character) are of primary importance, and that judgments about the rightness or wrongness of acts and/or the consequences of acts are secondary. One major criticism levied against virtue ethics is that its strong agent perspective prevents it from giving sufficiently specific advice about how to act in problematic situations. In this article, the development and structure of contemporary virtue ethics is presented, the challenge posed by the application problem is analyzed, and responses to it by applied virtue ethicists are assessed.

Virtue Ethics

C. Swanton, in International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences, 2001

Virtue ethics is a species of normative ethical theory generally seen as opposed to both Kantian ethics and Consequentialism. In its modern incarnations, it has been largely inspired by the eudaimonistic tradition of the ancient Greeks, and in particular Aristotle. However, we can expect further developments in virtue ethics which are inspired by other sources, such as Nietzsche and Hume. Virtue ethics is characterized by the centrality of character in normative ethical theory, where norms of excellence of character provide norms for both the good life in general and acting well and rightly. In virtue ethical traditions, norms of excellence of character are rich, and involve being well disposed in regard to reason, feelings, desires, motives, emotions, as well as action. Hence, the importance of the expression of fine inner states in virtue ethics. Problems for virtue ethics include the foundations of virtue, the universality of virtue, the relation between character and issues in applied ethics such as role obligations and right action generally, demands for codifiability and determinacy, and ‘character skepticism’ suggested by situationist psychology.

J. Sim, in Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics (Second Edition), 2012

Virtue Ethics

Within a virtue ethics approach, the emphasis is not on what one does but on the kind of person one is in terms of certain morally desirable character traits, such as compassion, benevolence, sensitivity, discretion, honesty, selflessness, and courage. The importance of such virtues can be underlined in two ways. First, it can be argued that character traits such as compassion and discretion are necessary in order for a person to recognize the moral demands of a particular situation; for example, it is only through possessing a measure of discretion that one will recognize a situation in which confidentiality is called for. Second, having identified the moral dimension in a situation, these same character traits may provide the necessary impetus or motivation to act: feelings of compassion not only allow one to identify a situation in which there is a moral demand to act to relieve another’s distress but also propel one to do so. In the process, virtues may enable a more sensitive and judicious application of the principles espoused by deontology or of the process of evaluating outcomes proposed by consequentialism. The notion of ‘caring’ that is central to health professionals’ practice has a clear resonance with virtue ethics.

Ethics

Peter J. Smith, John J. Hardt, in Developmental-Behavioral Pediatrics (Fourth Edition), 2009

Virtue Ethics

The central tenant of virtue ethics holds that the moral life is best promoted by attending to the moral agent herself or himself. Whereas deontologic ethics identifies and follows duties or obligations and utilitarian ethics attempts to maximize the good for the greatest number, virtue ethics seeks the moral formation of persons rather than the valuation of actions by paying attention to human virtue, friendship, moral wisdom, and discernment. As noted before, virtue ethics has deep roots in the classical world, and its philosophical origins are found in the Hippocratic Collection. Virtue ethics emphasizes the dynamic nature of ethical decisions, recognizing that individuals both shape and are shaped by what they choose to do in any given situation. Whereas virtue ethics flourished in the classical, philosophical world (Aquinas, 1920), its influence waned during the enlightenment. Virtue ethics has more recently experienced a revival in the 20th century in the work of moral philosopher Alasdair MacIntyre (1981) and others who have creatively recovered the work of their predecessors.

Critics of virtue ethics argue that it, like deontology and utilitarianism, cannot function within a morally plural society because of the lack of agreement on what virtues are actually worthy of promotion. Who decides what constitutes the good life and the good person among our ongoing disagreements about morality and value? Furthermore, the person-centered nature of this ethical system, insofar as it focuses on the moral agent rather than on obligations or principles, makes its content difficult to translate into codes, regulations, policies, or laws (Jonsen and Toulmin, 1988).

Deontology, Consequentialism, and Virtue Ethics

Source: Varieties of Virtue Ethics

Theory versus exploration in virtue ethics

Until sometime in the 1980s philosophers of ethics tended to think that the major alternatives in ethical theory were deontology and utilitarianism. Deontology is the view that some principle of obligation — Kant’s categorical imperative is the dominant contender — is the foundation of morality. Actions gain their moral worth by being generated from this foundation, and the virtuous person is one who is properly sensitive to the foundational principle (has “respect for the moral law”). Utilitarianism is the view that the goodness of actions derives not from their generating principle, but from the quality of their consequences. A classic example is J. S. Mill’s view that actions’ goodness comes from their fostering the general happiness or correcting unhappiness. Each of these theories offers its preferred basis of morality as the single ultimate and exclusive basis of moral goodness and rightness (which is not to deny that some thinkers offer “mixed” or “impure” theories that admit both bases on an equal footing, thus turning two monisms into a dualism, so to speak).

Sometime in the 1970s some philosophers got the bright idea of proposing a third alternative ethical theory, which they called “virtue ethics.” It was to have the same formal structure as the two classic modern theories, but be more plausible. So the basic idea was that virtue, not a principle of obligation or good outcomes and states of affairs, would be the foundation of ethical distinctions. Michael Slote well represents this proposal:

An agent-based approach to virtue ethics treats the moral or ethical status of acts as entirely derivative from independent and fundamental aretaic (as opposed to deontic) ethical characterizations of motives, character traits, or individuals… (2001, p. 5; italics added).

Eduardo Mendieta, in Encyclopedia of Violence, Peace, & Conflict (Second Edition), 2008

Deontology and the Pursuit of Moral Life

Virtue ethics, like Confucian ethics another form of virtue ethics, has as a fundamental assumption that humans are not born moral, but instead are socialized into morality. In both cases, the socialization entails acquiring certain social habits and living in accordance with communally sanctioned or proscribed mores and manners. These morals, in other words, do not travel well. What may be a virtue in one community may be a vice in another. Most importantly, how do we decide whether a virtue is in fact a moral excellence? The pursuit of virtue, in other words, does not produced morality, but the pursuit of morality leads us to virtue. It is in response to these doubts that Immanuel Kant developed his absolutist, deontological, and cognitivistic ethics. Kant begins with a Socratic question: “Is the pious loved by the gods because it’s pious? Or is it pious because it’s loved?” (Euthyphro 10a). According to Kant, and Socrates as well, we cannot judge something moral just because we deem it so, or have been told so. Nor can we derive morality from examples, role models, or paragons of morality, for in labeling them as such, we already operate with an inchoate notion of the moral. Kant argues that we must suspend all appeal to history, folklore, and religion in order to reflect on what we take to be truly moral. In order to do this Kant investigates the a priori assumptions of all moral action. He engages in what he calls a transcendental investigation, that is, he seeks to uncover the conditions of possibility without which morality would not make any sense. According to Kant, there are two indispensable presuppositions of morality: an absolutely free will and a rational nature. Morality is possible at all because humans are metaphysically (absolutely and not contingently) free and they have poor reason. Duty draws out for us this rational and free dimension of morality. A moral act, according to Kant, is one that is done without coercion, or without the fear of retaliation or some punishment. A moral act is one that is done for its own sake, or else it is a not a moral act but a contingent action aimed at achieving some specific end. When we act from duty, we act out of respect for the moral law. The moral worth of a moral act, therefore, is determined not by something external to it, but by the maxim (or principle that determines the will) according to which it is executed. If the moral worth of an act would be determined by something external, then the will would not be free and we would act out of inclination, desire, passion, or moral weakness. Duty thus reflects precisely how the moral is that which is universally necessary and commanded by the power of our reason. To act from duty is to act in accordance with reason and the determination of the free will. There is no other force or power that determines morality than the power of self-legislated duty. Duty in fact aims at what Kant called ‘categorical imperatives,’ which in contrast to hypothetical imperatives, are what must be done. While hypothetical imperatives are conditional, contingent, and aim at short-lived or narrow ends in such a way that the ends necessitate certain means, categorical imperatives are unconditional and unqualified and apply to all human conditions, and aim not at contingent and short-lived aims but at the very dignity of the human being. According to Kant in his Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, there is only one categorical imperative, which he formulates in this way: “Act only in accordance with that maxim through which you can at the same time will that it become a universal law.” Moral acts are only those that can be universalized. According to Kant this principle of the universability of moral law can be expressed in three other formulas: act in such a way that you treat the humanity of others as well as your own humanity, always as an end and never as a means; act in such a away that you always assume every ‘rational being’ to be a will that ‘legislates universal law,’ and act in such a way that you take yourself, and all other rational beings, to be members of a ‘kingdom of ends.’ The categorical imperative in its three versions essentially argues that morality is the expression of the moral autonomy of rational beings that legislate upon themselves laws that command their utmost respect. Morality, in other words, both expresses the dignity of the human being and commands its utmost reverence and respect. Notwithstanding its seeming rigor and absolutism, Kantianism is parsimonious and abstemious; it neither presuppose reference to specific cultural contexts and customs, nor does it offer a set of rules. The categorical imperative merely makes implicit that which we take to be indispensable and inalienable to morality; but it also offers us a North Star. As Kant noted in the conclusion to his Critique of Practical Reason: “Two things fill the mind with ever new and increasing admiration and reverence, the more often and more steadily one reflects on them: the starry heavens above and the moral law within me.” Like the lawfulness of the cosmos, which renders it both mysterious and awe-inspiring, the self-legislated lawfulness of morality, renders us admirable and sublime.

Source: Ethics of Physiotherapy

Varieties of Virtue Ethics

Source: THE ROUTLEDGE COMPANION TO VIRTUE ETHICS

  • Plato and the Ethics of Virtue
  • Aristotle’s Virtue Ethics
  • The Stoics Theory of Virtue
  • Hindu Virtue Ethics
  • Why Confucius’s Ethics is a Virtue Ethics
  • Mencius’s Virtue Ethics
  • Virue in Buddhist Ethical Traditions
  • Respect for Differences
  • Xunzi and Virtue Ethics
  • Consecrated Virtue
  • Thomas Aquinas
  • David Hume
  • Nietzsche and the Virtues
  • Eudaimonistic Virtue Ethics
  • Sentimentalist Virtue Ethics
  • Pluralistic Virue Ethics
  • Contemporary Christian Virtue Ethics
  • Contemporary Confucianism
  • Virtue Epistemology and Virue Ethics
  • Feminist Virtue Ethics
  • Agape and Virtue Ethics
  • Kant and Virtue Ethics
  • The Consequentialist Critique of Virtue Ethics
  • Virtue Ethics and Right Action
  • Virtue Ethics and Egoism
  • Models of Virtue
  • The Situationist Critique
  • Testing the Empathy-Altruism Hypothesis against Egoistic Alternatives
  • Care Ethics and Virtue Ethics
  • Roles and Virtues
  • Environmental Virtue Ethics
  • World Virtue Ethics
  • Virtue Ethics And Moral Education
  • Virtue Ethics As Political Philosophy
  • Law And Virtue
  • Virtue Ethics And Medicine
  • Business Ethics From A Virtue-Theoretic Perspective

Source: Virtue Ethics: A Contemporary Introduction

Source: A virtue ethics perspective on bioethics

Key features of virtue ethics

The most fundamental claim made by virtue ethics as a theory of right action is that reference to character and virtue are essential in the justification of right action (see Hursthouse 1999, pp. 28-31). A virtue-ethics-criterion right action can be stated initially in broad terms as holding that an action is right if and only if it is what an agent with a virtuous character would do in the circumstances (see Hursthouse, 1991, p. 225). That is, a right action is one that a virtuous person would do in the circumstances, and what makes the action right is that it is what a person with a virtuous character would do here.

An important qualification was subsequently made to this initial statement of a virtue-ethics-criterion of right action. In responding to concerns that even virtuous agents might occasionally act wrongly when they act contrary to their virtuous characters, Rosalind Hursthouse stipulated that the virtuous exemplar in the above criterion of right action must be understood to be acting in character (Hursthouse 1999, p. 28). Other variants of virtue ethics have recently been developed that specify the link between virtue and right action somewhat differently from that mentioned above. For example, Christine Swanton (2003) advocates what she calls a ‘target-centered’ approach, whereby virtuous actions are those that hit the target – realize the proper goal – of the virtue relevant to the context, and right actions are those that are overall virtuous in the circumstances in which the actual agent finds themselves (pp. 228-40). Nevertheless, the primacy given to character in both of these versions helps to distinguish virtue ethics from standard forms of Kantianism, Utilitarianism, and Consequentialism, whereby actions are justified according to rules or outcomes.

Of course, if virtue ethics is to guide and justify actions, this criterion clearly needs to be supplemented by an account of which character-traits count as virtues. (Similarly, a rule-utilitarian criterion of right action needs to be supplemented by an account of which universally adopted rules maximize utility.) Nevertheless, the above formulations already highlight a key difference between virtue ethics and standard Kantian and Utilitarian approaches, whereby the rightness of an act is determined by whether the act is in accordance with certain rules, or by whether it maximizes expected utility, respectively. For neither of those approaches, as standardly defined, make reference to character essential to the justification of right action. For example, Utilitarians like Henry Sidgwick (1981, p. 227) saw virtues such as generosity, gratitude, and courage as instrumentally valuable, insofar as they help to bring about the pleasure and happiness of sentient beings, or a life of ‘desirable consciousness’ (especially in circumstances where we have insufficient time to deliberate).

It is important to clarify that doing what the virtuous agent would do involves not merely the performance of certain acts, but requires acting from certain dispositions and (in many cases) certain motives. For example, acting as someone with the virtue of benevolence would act involves not only providing assistance to another person but also includes having and acting from a genuine concern for their well-being, and a disposition to have and act from that concern in particular kinds of situations. As Aristotle (1980, VI, 13, 1144b26-9) put it, “It is not merely the state in accordance with the right rule, but the state that implies the presence of the right rule, that is virtue”. Acting as the virtuous agent would act typically involves acting from certain motives – though one can act justly from a variety of motives, so long as one acts from a disposition that incorporates an appropriate sense of justice. Every virtue can be thought to embody a regulative ideal, involving the internalization of a certain conception of excellence such that one is able to adjust one’s motivation and conduct so that they conform to that standard. Indeed, Julia Annas (2011) has argued that the nature of virtues must be understood by grasping how virtues are acquired, in the way that skills like piano-playing are acquired. That is, virtues should be viewed as comparable to skills “that exhibit the practical intelligence of the skilled craftsperson or athlete” (Annas 2011, p. 169). Annas argues that “part of the attraction of an ethics of virtue has always been the point that virtue is familiar and recognizable by all, so it would still be a damaging result if virtue is hopelessly unattainable by all but a few”(p. 173; see also Russell 2009).

A key difference between virtue ethics and standard Utilitarian and Kantian ethical theories is the close connection typically drawn by virtue ethics between motive and rightness. Most forms of Utilitarianism and Kantianism hold that, generally speaking, one can act rightly, whatever one’s motivation – so long as one maximizes expected utility or acts in accordance with duty, one has done the right thing, whether one’s motives were praiseworthy, reprehensible, or neutral. However, as we have seen, virtue ethics typically holds that acting rightly (in most situations) requires acting from a particular sort of motivation, since this is part of what is involved in doing what a virtuous person would do in the circumstances. Indeed, Michael Slote (2001, 2007) has developed an ‘agent-based’ virtue ethics, whereby an action is right if and only if it is done from a virtuous motive, such as benevolence. Acting from the virtuous motive of benevolence, in Slote’s view, is not simply acting to help another from a warm-hearted feeling towards them, but involves seeking via an active capacity for empathy to understand their plight, and monitoring one’s action to see that it is actually helping.

Distinguishing virtue ethics more fully from contemporary versions of Kantian and Utilitarian approaches requires filling in the details about which character-traits count as virtues (see Oakley 1996). So, just as Kantians and Utilitarians need to detail their general criteria of rightness by specifying which rules we are to act in accordance with, or what expected utility consists of, virtue ethicists must likewise provide details about what the virtues are. For virtue ethics to be capable of guiding action, the criterion of right action outlined above needs to be completed with an account of the virtues. The distinctiveness of virtue ethics compared to other theories is brought out more fully when we consider the ways in which advocates of the approach ground the normative conceptions in the character of the virtuous agent.

Many virtue ethicists hold the Aristotelian view that virtues are character traits that we need to live humanly flourishing lives. In this view, developed principally by Foot (1978, 2001) and Hursthouse (1987, 1999), benevolence and justice are virtues because they are part of an interlocking web of intrinsic goods – which includes friendship, integrity and knowledge – without which we cannot have eudaimonia. According to Aristotle, the characteristic activity of human beings is the exercise of our rational capacity, and only by living virtuously is our rational capacity to guide our lives expressed in an excellent way. Construing virtues as character traits that humans need to lourish, Hursthouse argues that what makes a character trait a virtue in humans is that it serves well the following four ‘naturalistic’ ends: individual survival, individual characteristic enjoyment and freedom from pain, the good functioning of the social group, and the continuance of the species (1999, pp. 200-1, 208, 248). Aristotle argues that each virtue can be understood as involving hitting the mean between two vices – for example, the virtue of courage is the mean between the vices of cowardice and rashness. However, Aristotle realizes that telling us to aim at a mean between excess and defect is vague: “if a man had only this knowledge he would be none the wiser – eg, we should not know what sort of medicines to apply to our body if some were to say ‘all those which the medical art prescribes, and which agree with the practice of one who possesses the art’ ” (1980, VI, 1, 1138b29-33). So Aristotle proceeds to develop his account of ethical judgment as practical wisdom (phronesis), as a way of explaining how virtues can guide actions.

A different approach to grounding the virtues, pioneered by Michael Slote (1992), rejects the eudaimonist idea of Aristotle that virtues are found by considering what humans need in order to lourish, and instead derives virtues from our commonsense views about what character traits we typically find admirable – as exemplified in the lives of figures such as Albert Einstein and Mother Teresa – whether or not those traits help an individual to flourish. Swanton (2003) also rejects Aristotelian eudaimonism, and argues that virtues are dispositions to respond to morally significant features of objects in an excellent way, whether or not such dispositions are good for the person who has them. For example, Swanton (2203, pp. 82-3) argues that a great artist’s creative drive can be a virtue, even if this drive leads the artist to suffer bipolar disorder – such an artist’s creative drive need not bring flourishing, but Swanton argues it is nevertheless an excellent way of responding to value, and can certainly result in a life that is justifiably regarded as successful in some sense.

My Related Posts

The Great Chain of Being

Indra’s Net: On Interconnectedness

Mind, Consciousness and Quantum Entanglement

Consciousness of Cosmos: A Fractal, Recursive, Holographic Universe

Cosmic Mirror Theory

Fractal Geometry and Hindu Temple Architecture

Geometry of Consciousness

Truth, Beauty, and Goodness

Truth, Beauty, and Goodness: Integral Theory of Ken Wilber

The Aesthetics of Charles Sanders Peirce

The Good, the True, and the Beautiful

Aesthetics and Ethics

Aesthetics and Ethics: At the Intersection

Phenomenology and Symbolic Interactionism

Meta Integral Theories: Integral Theory, Critical Realism, and Complex Thought

On Classical Virtues

On Holons and Holarchy

Human Rights and Human Development

Third and Higher Order Cybernetics

Arts and Moral Philosophy

Psychology of Happiness: Value of Storytelling and Narrative Plays

Key Sources of Research

Ethics of Physiotherapy

J. Sim,

in Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics (Second Edition), 2012

https://www.sciencedirect.com/topics/psychology/virtue-ethic

“Introduction” ,


van Hooft, Stan , 

in The Handbook of Virtue Ethics 

ed. Stan van Hooft , Nafsika Athanassoulis , Jason Kawall , Justin Oakley , Nicole Saunders and Liezl Van Zyl 

(Abingdon: Routledge, 27 Nov 2013 ), accessed 01 Oct 2022 , Routledge Handbooks Online.

https://www.routledgehandbooks.com/doi/10.4324/9781315729053.ch1#S1

Virtue Ethics: A Contemporary Introduction

By Liezl van Zyl

Routledge, 2019

On Virtue Ethics

1st Edition

by Rosalind Hursthouse

ISBN-13: 978-0198238188

ISBN-10: 0198238185

Intelligent Virtue

1st Edition

by Julia Annas (Author)

ISBN-13: 978-0199228775

ISBN-10: 0199228779

The Cambridge Companion to Virtue Ethics

(Cambridge Companions to Philosophy) 0th Edition

by Daniel C. Russell (Editor)

ISBN-13: 978-0521171748
ISBN-10: 0521171741

The Routledge Companion to Virtue Ethics

(Routledge Philosophy Companions) 1st Edition

by Lorraine Besser-Jones (Editor), Michael Slote (Editor)

ISBN-13: 978-1138478220
ISBN-10: 1138478229

Virtue Ethics

(Oxford Readings in Philosophy) 1st Edition

by Roger Crisp (Editor), Michael Slote (Editor)

ISBN-13: 978-0198751885
ISBN-10: 0198751885

Natural Goodness

1st Edition

by Philippa Foot (Author)

ISBN-13: 978-0199265473

ISBN-10: 019926547X

Kant: Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

(Cambridge Texts in the History of Philosophy) 2nd Edition

by Mary Gregor (Translator), Jens Timmermann (Translator), Christine M. Korsgaard (Introduction)

ISBN-13: 978-1107401068
ISBN-10: 1107401062

Nicomachean Ethics

Third Edition, third edition

by Aristotle (Author), Terence Irwin (Translator)

ISBN-13: 978-1624668159
ISBN-10: 1624668151

Utilitarianism

Second Edition

by John Stuart Mill (Author), George Sher (Editor)

ISBN-13: 978-0872206052
ISBN-10: 087220605X

Virtue Ethics

Science Direct Page

https://www.sciencedirect.com/topics/psychology/virtue-ethic

Virtue Ethics: A Critical Reader

Daniel Statman (ed.)
Georgetown University Press (1997)
ISBN: 9780878402205

ISBN: 9780878402212 (0878402217)

http://press.georgetown.edu/book/georgetown/virtue-ethics

https://philpapers.org/rec/STAVE

Varieties of Virtue Ethics

edited by David Carr, James Arthur, Kristján Kristjánsson

Virtue Ethics and Consequentialism in Early Chinese Philosophy

By Bryan van Norden

The Virtue Ethics of Hume and Nietzsche

By Christine Swanton


Virtue Ethics and the Chinese Confucian Tradition 

Chapter

in Book Virtue Ethics and Confucianism

By PHILIP J. IVANHOE

Edition 1st Edition, First Published 2013, Imprint Routledge

eBook ISBN 9780203522653

https://www.taylorfrancis.com/chapters/edit/10.4324/9780203522653-11/virtue-ethics-chinese-confucian-tradition-philip-ivanhoe

Varieties of Virtue Ethics

Robert C. Roberts
Distinguished Professor of Ethics Emeritus, Baylor University

From James Arthur, David Carr, and Kristján Kristjánsson, eds., Varieties of Virtue Ethics (Palgrave Macmillan, 2017)

THE ETHICS OF THE NODE VERSUS THE ETHICS OF THE DYAD? RECONCILING VIRTUE ETHICS AND CONTRACTUALISM*

Pursey P. M. A. R. Heugens
Muel Kaptein
J. (Hans) van Oosterhout

ORGANIZATION STUDIES 27(3): 391-411.

After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory

Third Edition Paperback – Download: Adobe Reader, March 6, 2007

First Ed – 1981

by Alasdair MacIntyre (Author)

A Short History of Ethics: A History of Moral Philosophy from the Homeric Age to the Twentieth Century,

Second Edition Paperback – Download: Adobe Reader, January 15, 1998

by Alasdair MacIntyre (Author)

Virtue Ethics

(2018) 

Rhetoric Review, 37:4, 321-392, 

DOI: 10.1080/07350198.2018.1497882

https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/full/10.1080/07350198.2018.1497882

A Problem Based Reading of Nussbaum’s Virtue Ethics

by John C. Brady

Epoche Magazine

Issue #16 September 2018

https://epochemagazine.org/16/a-problem-based-reading-of-nussbaums-virtue-ethics/

Being Virtuous and Doing the Right Thing.

Annas, J. (2013).

In R. Shafer-Landau, Ethical Theory: An Anthology (2nd ed., pp. 676–686). West Sussex: Wiley-Blackwell.

Normative Virtue Ethics.

Hursthouse, R. (2013).

In R. Shafer-Landau, Ethical Theory: An Anthology (2nd ed., pp. 645–652). West Sussex: Wiley-Blackwell.

Virtue Ethics: A Misleading Category. 

Nussbaum, M. (1999).

The Journal Of Ethics3(3), 163–201. doi: 10.1023/a:1009829301765

Non-Relative Virtues: An Aristotelian Approach.

Nussbaum, M. (2013).

In R. Shafer-Landau, Ethical Theory: An Anthology (2nd ed., pp. 630–644). West Sussex: Wiley-Blackwell.

Varieties of Virtue Ethics in Philosophy, Social Science and Theology,

Oriel College, Oxford, January 8th–10th, 2015

The third annual conference of the Jubilee Centre for Character and Virtues, University of Birmingham. UK

https://www.jubileecentre.ac.uk/502/conferences/varieties-of-virtue-ethics

Which Variety of Vitue Ethics?

Julia Annas

This is an unpublished conference paper for the 3rd Annual Jubilee Centre for Character and Virtues conference at Oriel College, Oxford University, Thursday 8th – Saturday 10th January 2015.

Why Confucius’s Ethics is a Virtue Ethics

May Sim

This is an unpublished conference paper for the 3rd Annual Jubilee Centre for Character and Virtues conference at Oriel College, Oxford University, Thursday 8th – Saturday 10th January 2015.

Normative Virtue Ethics

Rosalind Hursthouse

Click to access hursthouse_-_normative_virtue_ethics.pdf

A virtue ethics perspective on bioethics

Una perspectiva de la ética de la virtud en bioética

Justin Oakley

Centre for Human Bioethics, Monash University, Melbourne, Australia

Received 10 March 2015; accepted 27 March 2015

BIOETHICS UPdate 1 (2015) 41-53

A Virtue Ethical Account of Right Action

Christine Swanton

Ethics

Volume 112, Number 1 October 2001

https://doi.org/10.1086/322742

https://www.journals.uchicago.edu/doi/pdf/10.1086/322742

The Virtue of “Virtue Ethics” in Business and Business Education

https://www.semanticscholar.org/paper/The-Virtue-of-“Virtue-Ethics”-in-Business-and-Wittmer-O’Brien/b140b4cd37d9264e33425851cb21cbacd1063289

Modern Moral Philosophy

https://www.semanticscholar.org/paper/Modern-Moral-Philosophy-Anscombe/41dd2aaa779faf3d40599a6711cabd07284d7775

Toward a Synthesis of Confucianism and Aristotelianism

Bryan W Van Norden

Chapter in Book Virtue Ethics and Confucianism
Edited by Stephen C. Angle and Michael Slote

2013

https://www.academia.edu/12762325/Toward_a_Synthesis_of_Confucianism_and_Aristotelianism

BWVN Virtue Ethics and Confucianism

Bryan W Van Norden

Chapter 5 in Book

https://www.academia.edu/12762328/BWVN_Virtue_Ethics_and_Confucianism


Why Virtue Ethics? Action and motivation in virtue ethics

Norah Woodcock*

McGill University

Aporia Vol. 19 No. 1

Virtue Ethics

First published Fri Jul 18, 2003; substantive revision Thu Dec 8, 2016

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy

https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ethics-virtue/

Virtue Ethics

Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Virtue Ethics

Wikipedia

https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Virtue_ethics

AN INTRODUCTION TO WESTERN ETHICAL THOUGHT: ARISTOTLE, KANT, UTILITARIANISM

Heather Wilburn, Ph.D.

Virtue ethics of clinical research

Letter to the Editor

María Pérez‐Piñar1, Luis Ayerbe1,2

1The Westborough Road Health Centre, Westcliff‐on‐Sea, Essex, SS0 9PT, 2Centre for Primary Care and Public Health, Queen Mary University of London, London, United Kingdom

Dr. Luis Ayerbe, Centre for Primary Care and Public Health, Queen Mary University of London, Yvonne Carter Building, 58, Turner Street, London E1 2AB, United Kingdom. E‐mail: l.garcia‐morzon@qmul.ac.uk

The Handbook of Virtue Ethics

Stan van Hooft

2014

https://www.routledge.com/The-Handbook-of-Virtue-Ethics/Hooft/p/book/9781844656394

VIRTUE ETHICS

Michael Slote

Virtue Ethics

Speaker: David Massey

Indian Hill Schools

“Virtue Ethics” 

Julia Annas

The Oxford Handbook of Ethical Theory, edited by David Copp and published in 2007.

A virtue ethics approach to moral dilemmas in medicine

P Gardiner

J Med Ethics 2003;29:297–302

Virtue Ethics

Klement

Univ of Mass, MA

Virtue Ethics

Publisher: Wiley-Blackwell

Copyright Date:  2002

Author (Faculty Member):  Stephen Darwall

Virtue Ethics collects, for the first time, the main classical sources and the central contemporary expressions of virtue ethics approach to normative ethical theory. Includes classic essays by Aristotle, Francis Hutcheson and David Hume, and recent reactions to this work by philosophers including Philippa Foot, John McDowell, Alasdair MacIntyre, Annette Baier, Rosalind Hursthouse, and Michael Slote. With an introduction by Stephen Darwall as well as a contemporary discussion on character and virtue by Gary Watson.

https://philosophy.yale.edu/publications/virtue-ethics

Virtue Ethics

CHAPTER 12

THE ELEMENTS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY

James Rachels and Stuart Rachels

Click to access james_rachels_and_stuart_rachels_virtue_ethics.pdf

Ethical Theories

The Arthur W. Page Center Public Relations Ethics

Penn State

https://pagecentertraining.psu.edu/public-relations-ethics/introduction-to-public-relations-ethics/lesson-1/ethical-theories/

Consumer Moral Leadership

January 2010

Sue L.T. Mcgregor
Mount Saint Vincent University

https://www.researchgate.net/publication/267220449_Consumer_Moral_Leadership

Aesthetics and Ethics

Aesthetics and Ethics

  • Aesthetics and Ethics are interdependent on each other
  • Steps to an Ecology of mind

Why do good? Why be moral?

  • Do good because its a good value for a virtuous person
  • Do good out of compassion and love for others
  • Do good because it is good for one’s self
  • Do good because world outside is none other than yourself. (Vedantic Perspective)

Aesthetics

  • of Design
  • of Arts
  • of Performance Arts
  • of Rituals
  • of Traditions
  • of Narrative Arts
  • of Culture
  • of Architecture
  • of Actions
  • of Thoughts
  • of Senses
  • of Emotions
  • of Values
  • of Experience

Key Terms

  • Virtues
  • Values
  • Aesthetics
  • Arts
  • Morals
  • Ethics
  • Good ness
  • Art and Morals
  • Aesthetics and Ethics
  • Beauty and Goodness
  • Ist person and 2nd Person
  • Integral Theory
  • Ken Wilber
  • Self, Culture, Nature
  • I, We, It/Its
  • Immanual Kant
  • Wittgenstein
  • Sameness and Otherness
  • Difference
  • Boundaries and Networks
  • Hierarchy and Networks
  • Plato and Aristotle
  • Action Learning
  • Reflexive Action
  • Social Ethics
  • Communities of Goodness
  • Environmental Ethics
  • Inter-objectivity
  • Inter-subjectivity
  • Subject and Object
  • Phenomenology and Hermenutics
  • Virtue Ethics
  • Development and Relations
  • Internal vs External
  • Individual vs Collective
  • Culture, Society, and Ethics
  • Narrative Arts
  • Intentions and Actions
  • Sewa and Service
  • Altruism
  • Philosophy of Arts
  • Aesthetics of living culture
  • Traditions, Rituals, and Culture
  • Classical Education
  • Arts and Humanities
  • Dance, Music and Performance Arts
  • Universals
  • Transcendentals
  • Ethnomethodology
  • Nondual Vedanta (Advait Vedanta)
  • Steps to an Ecology of Mind
  • Value Theory
  • Virtue Theory
  • Art Criticism
  • Taste, Style, Manners
  • Relational
  • Aesthetics and Relatedness
  • Consciousness
  • Nondual Awareness
  • Interconnectedness

Ethics as Aesthetics: Foucault’S Critique of Moralization of Ethics

This study found a new idea of ethics to bridge the gap between morality and aesthetics. This new idea is called aesthetics morality. This study concluded as follows: 1) ethics as morality is in the form of teleology, deontology and virtue ethics; 2) ethics is a synthesis of aesthetics and morality; and 3) ethics is aesthetics in the form of care of the self. 

Ethics as Style:
Wittgenstein’s Aesthetic Ethics and Ethical Aesthetics

An inquiry into Wittgenstein’s ethics and aesthetics has to start with the following questions: Can an aesthetics and/or ethics be extracted from his philosophical texts at all? If yes, what kind of aesthetics and/or ethics does Wittgenstein offer beyond his well-known aphoristic comments on the subject? Finally, how can we understand the meaning of his claim that ‘‘ethics and aesthetics are one’’? This article responds to the above questions by presenting an account of Wittgenstein’s ethical aesthetics and aesthetic ethics, elucidating both through the prism of his notion of style as ‘‘general necessity seen sub specie eterni.’’ It explains how logical necessity implodes within the limits of propositional language to open onto the realm of style, within which ethical necessity is to be understood in terms of aesthetic life-form and aesthetic expression is to be understood in terms of ethical enactment.

Es ist klar, daß sich die Ethik nicht aussprechen läßt. Die Ethik ist transzendental.
(Ethik und Ästhetik sind Eins.)

[It is clear that ethics cannot be expressed. Ethics is transcendental.
(Ethics and aesthetics are one.)]
Ludwig Wittgenstein

Aesthetics and Ethics: Essays at the Intersection

This book brings together a number of new essays in an area of growing concern, namely the intersection or overlap of aesthetics and ethics. Recent developments aside, for the past thirty years or so in Anglo-American philosophy, aesthetics and ethics have been pursued in relative isolation, with aesthetics being generally regarded as the poorer, if flashier, cousin. The attention aestheticians have recently given to moral aspects of art and art criticism, and that ethicists have recently paid to aesthetic aspects of moral life and moral evaluation, give hope of ending this rather artificial isolation, though without necessarily forcing us to accede in Wittgenstein’s gnomic dictum that “ethics and aesthetics are one.”

The intersection of aesthetics and ethics can be understood to comprise three spheres of inquiry. The first is that of problems or presuppositions common to aesthetics and ethics, the two traditional branches of value theory. The second is that of ethical issues in aesthetics, or in the practice of art. And the third sphere is that of aesthetic issues in ethics, theoretical and applied.

As it turns out, the concerns of the present collection do not span the full intersection of aesthetics and ethics as just explained. For reasons of both unity and manageability, the decision was made to foreground aesthetics in the present venture. The result is that the essays fall under the first and second, but not the third ways of understanding the intersection of the two fields.

2 – Three versions of objectivity: aesthetic, moral, and scientific

How does the objective validity of aesthetic judgments compare with the objective validity of moral judgments and scientific beliefs? There are two traditional answers. According to one, aesthetic and moral appraisals both utterly lack the cognitive authority of scientific inquiry, since neither kind of appraiser has access to a fact independent of her own judgments and neither is in a position to claim that all who are adequately qualified would share her judgment. For example, emotivists deprive both aesthetic and moral judgments of both kinds of objectivity. According to the other tradition, well-formed aesthetic and moral judgments have the same cognitive authority as wellformed scientific beliefs, because in all three realms the judgment maker is often in a position to assert a truth independent of her judgments, in a claim to which all adequately qualified inquirers would assent. For example, Kant puts the three realms on a par in both ways.

Each of these traditions has distinctive liabilities, which jointly suggest the need to explore a third alternative. The debunking tradition, depriving both aesthetic and moral judgments of all the authority of science, is hard to reconcile with the pervasive aspirations to truth and interests in impersonal argument of apparently rational people engaged in moral and aesthetic judgment. On the other hand, the claims to universality in the elevating tradition often seem wishful thinking.

Elsewhere, I have defended a view of morality and science that rejects the association in both traditions of rational access to appraiser-independent truth with epistemic universality.

5 – Art, narrative, and moral understanding

With much art, we are naturally inclined to speak of it in moral terms. Especially when considering things like novels, short stories, epic poems, plays, and movies, we seem to fall effortlessly into talking about them in terms of ethical significance – in terms of whether or which characters are virtuous or vicious, and about whether the work itself is moral or immoral, and perhaps whether it is sexist or racist. Undoubtedly, poststructuralists will choke on my use of the phrase “naturally inclined,” just because they do not believe that humans are naturally inclined toward anything. But that general premise is as needlessly strong a presupposition as it is patently false. And, furthermore, I hope to show that my talk of natural inclinations is hardly misplaced here, for we are prone to respond to the types of works in question in the language of moral assessment exactly because of the kinds of things they are.

Moreover, we do not merely make moral assessments of artworks as a whole and characters in particular; it is also the case that these moral assessments are variable. That is, we find some artworks to be morally good, while some others are not; some are exemplary, while some others are vicious and perhaps even pernicious; and finally other works may not appear to call for either moral approbation or opprobrium. So, though we very frequently do advance moral assessments of artworks, it is important to stress that we have a gamut of possible evaluative judgments at our disposal: from the morally good to the bad to the ugly, to the morally indifferent and the irrelvant.

Problems at the Intersection of Aesthetics and Ethics

The Intersection of Aesthetics and Ethics

Ever since the publication of Kant’s Critique of Judgment, the concept of taste has been severed from its moral sense and reduced to a merely aesthetic one.1 Since then two trends have predominated in moral philosophy. The first is a rationalist view of ethics, which proposes the need to subsume particular actions under universal laws. Deontological and utilitarian theories both have this paradigm in common. The second is the refraction of this position, which marginalizes any discussion of moral feeling as a psychological question of emotivism or subjectivism.2 This trend of positivism dismisses feelings as mere emotive states, questions of psychology, subjective, and therefore not binding.

In order to recapture the aesthetic dimensions of moral experience, one needs a view of aesthetics that is not limited to reflections on the beautiful and sublime in nature or art and that is not reducible to an allegiance to taste and manners; and one needs a continuity principle that enables reflection on morality to be true to experience. Two process philosophers, Alfred North Whitehead and John Dewey, present a metaphysics of experience which enriches ethics by illustrating the aesthetic dimensions of moral experience. Where the traditions outlined above view reason as the pivotal faculty in navigating the moral landscape, process philosophy emphasizes the aesthetic categories of feeling and imagination as operative in moral experience.

Those skeptical of “aestheticizing morality” often invoke the show-stopping reference to the Nazi Regime, one which consciously and politically recruited aesthetic ideals toward the crystallization of immorality.3 This is the Reductio ad Hitlerum to which the title refers. Fascism and Nazism in particular habituated a marriage between politics and aesthetics, and took up the goal of making politics a triumphant and beautiful spectacle.4 Art, music, and aesthetic symbols were recruited as instruments toward fulfilling this goal.5 Nazi Germany held “countless historical pageants, Volk festivals, military parades, propaganda films, art exhibitions and [erected] grandiose buildings”6 in order to exemplify “the fascist desire to invent mythic imperial pasts and futures,”7 while stirring the passions of the people for its war efforts. The Nazis denounced any allegiance to liberal political texts such as the Versailles Treaty “in favor of decisive political action based on fatal aesthetic criteria — beautiful vs. ugly, healthy vs. degenerate, German vs. Jew.”8 It is warranted to invoke this as the problem for those who “aestheticize” morality. The Nazi problematic, illustrated by an analysis of two films surrounding the immorality of the Nazi Regime, James Ivory’s The Remains of the Day (1993) and István Szabó’s Taking Sides (2001) illuminates the limitations and failures of the tendency to “aestheticize” morality. These films help show the nuances that reside at this tense intersection between aesthetics and ethics. However, tension between aesthetics and ethics, as depicted by the two films, dissolves once one’s understanding of aesthetics ceases to be reductive and narrow.

The aesthetic dimensions of moral experience in the philosophies of Alfred North Whitehead and John Dewey provide a basis for defining the continuity between ethics and aesthetics. For Whitehead, an aesthetic vision which builds on insights of his descriptive metaphysics enables us to see moral experience as aesthetic. For Dewey, the imagination works on the possibilities at hand in order to resolve morally problematic situations, and the grist for the imagination’s mill is experiential, perceptual, and aesthetic, not merely rational or conceptual. Thus, the broad use of aesthetics advocated herein enables us to draw moral distinctions in the face of Nazi atrocities instead of blindly serving the ideal of artistic creation. Nor does it reduce aesthetics to a fetish for manners. Rather, as including imagination, perception, taste, and emotion, an aesthetic orientation to ethics can encompass the limits posed by these films, and it can morally condemn the Nazi Regime and avoid the Hitler-reductio.

A.N. Whitehead at the Intersection

A sketch of Whitehead’s metaphysics is necessary in order to show how the foundations for moral action may be subsumed under the category of aesthetic experience. According to Whitehead’s systematic metaphysics, the world is a process of becoming. It is ultimately composed of self-creating “actual occasions.”9 The act of self-creation is the “concrescence” of an actual entity, “the final real things of which the world is made up.”10 Thus an “entity” describes an occasion or event in the mode of concrescense, the act of an occasion having prehended its environment. Events create themselves by virtue of their interdependence. The mode of relation each entity has toward others and toward its possibilities in general is “feeling.” “Prehensions” are the feelings which each entity has of its environment, which includes the entire universe, as each entity pulsates and vibrates throughout the cosmos in its process of self-creation.11 Since Whitehead holds that relations are more fundamental than substance, these prehensions constitute the actual entity. Where in traditional metaphysics, substance is primary and the relations among substances are described as secondary attributes, in Whitehead’s description entities are internally related, constituted by their relations. In this process metaphysics, relations are not secondary but primary in that they constitute the entities. When an actual entity prehends its environment, the entity constitutes itself and makes itself what it is.12Each entity serves as the subject of its own becoming and the “superject” of others, imparting itself to other entities in their becoming.13 Actual entities, in process metaphysics, are events, occasions in time, and always situated in a complex, interdependent environment of other entities. Thus, Whitehead’s speculative metaphysics is relational, not atomistic.

This speculative picture of reality lends itself to reflections on moral experience, including an account of Whitehead’s theory of value. In Process and Reality, Whitehead’s theory of value uses strong aesthetic language. He describes intensity of experience as “strength of beauty”: the degree of feeling in an occasion’s prehension of its environment. 14 Further, as John Cobb notes, “The chief ingredients [to beautiful experience] are emotional.”15 The actual entity prehends its environment, feeling its aesthetic surrounding in a chiefly emotional comportment. Because the locus of value is the intensity and harmony of an experience and the emotional sphere contributes chiefly to beautiful experience, emotion need not be corralled by reason, but channeled toward the achievement of beauty. Further, Whitehead shows that philosophers who treat feelings as merely private are mistakenly taking a phase of concrescence to be the whole of experience. For Whitehead, “there is no element in the universe capable of pure privacy.”16 The impossibility of pure privacy undermines the conceptual option of positivists and others who atomize and privatize feeling in order to dismiss its role in moral experiences as subjectivism or emotivism, both of which result in relativism.

Moral experience and aesthetic experience work dialectically: “The function of morality is to promote beauty in experience,”17 but emotions inform morality by adding to the value of experience. Sensation and emotion are not passively received, private reifications; instead, they seamlessly compose the environment we inhabit. Cobb contends that “the purely aesthetic impulse and the moral one exist in a tension” and that “the good aimed at for others is an aesthetic good — the strength of beauty of their experience.”18

Whitehead writes:

In our own relatively high grade human existence, this doctrine of feelings and their subject is best illustrated by our notion of moral responsibility. The subject is responsible for being what it is in virtue of its feelings. It is also derivatively responsible for the consequences of its existence because they flow from its feelings.19

That our existence flows from our feelings reveals the foundation of moral action on aesthetic, αἰσθηματικός, “sensuous” experience. When Whitehead contends that our moral actions flow from our feelings, he places a primacy upon our emotional comportment. The main contribution we make to others is our spirit or attitude.20This spirit is a comportment and temperament, an angle of vision. If our vision is broad and seeks to contribute to the strength of beauty of others’ experience, it is continuous with moral experience. Moral vision is attitudinal and acting according to calculation, deliberation, and reason, while poor in spirit, is not moral action. Whitehead posits a theory of value where our goal is to realize a strength of beauty in our immediate occasions of action. Taking a calculating attitude towards future consequences endangers this goal.21 It is misleading to think that one can calculate rationally toward that best action.22 Rather, such moral rationalism can justify activity that we feel is inhumane, evil, ugly, unjust, and wrong. It can sever means from ends and justify that which our sentiments would impeach.

Whitehead’s speculative metaphysics, by using humanistic and aesthetic language, includes a description of moral experience. Occasions of activity become harmonious with their environment by acting in the service of beauty. Actions emanate from feelings, and right action is not the function of rational deliberation, but of whole-part relations, of fitting the variety of detail and contrast under the unity of an aesthetic concrescence. Whitehead’s is a seductive account of reality, but nowhere in it do we find something like evil. Those skeptical of such an aesthetic description of moral experience may ask, “Where is the Holocaust in this picture?” Thus, below a recourse to two films about Nazism, aesthetics, and morality enables the skeptic to reexamine the continuity between ethics and aesthetics and consider a broader, less reductive, understanding of aesthetics itself. Before addressing this question, another account of how process philosophy maintains continuity between ethics and aesthetics is in order.

John Dewey at the Intersection

In order to outline Dewey’s description of the aesthetic dimensions of moral experience, a cursory illustration of the continuity at work in his metaphysics of experience and theory of inquiry is in order. Dewey described the generic traits of human experience as both precarious and stable.23 Indeterminate situations produce the conditions of instability.24 Subjecting a precarious situation to inquiry constitutes it as problematic, enabling an agent to identify possible means of resolving the situations within the constituent features of the uniquely given situation. Our employment of imaginative intelligence directs our activity in an effort to resolve the situation by rearranging the conditions of indeterminacy toward settlement and unification.25

In a manner similar to Whitehead, Dewey refers to the creative integration of the entire complex situation with the term “value.”26 One constituent in the activity of unifying the problematic situation is the end-in-view, which functions as a specific action coordinating all other factors involved in the institution and resolution of the problem. The value is the integration and unification of the situation. When the end-in-view functions successfully toward the integration of the situation, the resultant unification is a “consummatory phase of experience.”27 Dewey wrote, “Values are naturalistically interpreted as intrinsic qualities of events in their consummatory reference.”28 Their naturalistic interpretation renders the experience of value and the process of valuation continuous with other natural processes. That is, the ends-in-view, whether or not these are moral ideals, do not exist antecedent to inquiry into the complex, historical, and uniquely given situation, as the rationalists would have it. The general traits of moral experience are found within aesthetic experience — dispelling the need dichotomize experience into the cognitive and the emotional — because values are qualities of events.

The ability to examine the aesthetic dimensions of moral experience depends on the way Dewey defines an aesthetically unified and integrated experience as consummatory. The consummation refers to the experience of the unification of meaning of all of the phases of a complex experience.29 Thus, the aesthetic experience gives a holistic meaning to the precariousness of its parts. The value of an experience, including moral value, refers, as in Whitehead’s description, to whole-part relations and the unification of various elements therein.

Art is the skill of giving each phase its meaning in light of the whole. Art unifies each function of the experience, giving reflection, action, desire, and imagination an integrated relation both to each other and to the possibility of meaningful resolution.30 Thus, Dewey refuses to parcel out a separate faculty at work in isolation in any meaningful experience, whether that is reason in cognition or emotion in sympathetic attention to a friend. The consummatory experience is one in which we employ imaginative intelligence in appropriating aesthetic, felt elements of experience above and beyond their immediacy and one in which the instability of their immediacy is seen imaginatively as a possibility toward its meaningful integration.31

Thus, artful conduct includes moral conduct, but in a way that both avoids the need to import ideals transcendent to our experience and gives moral ideals their reality in the meaning that ensues in the consequences of their enactment. The features of artful conduct inherent in moral behavior concern the ability to see possibilities in the elements of precariousness, “to see the actual in light of the possible.”32 Where the rationalist searches for a universal concept to justify a given, isolated action whose justification could be known but not felt, the moral imagination enables the agent to envision in her environment the constituent possibilities in order to reconstruct the situation.

Both Whitehead and Dewey treat moral experience as continuous with the aesthetic experience of intensity, meaning, unification, and harmony found in the consummatory phase of experience, or in Whitehead’s terms, in concrescence. Both treat vision and imagination, not calculative rationality, as operative in navigating morally problematic situations. The general trend running through these process philosophies that maintains continuity between ethics and aesthetics concerns whole-part relations. The individual in morally charged situations must harmonize her particular conduct to the whole of her environment broadly construed. She must imaginatively find the proper fit of her conduct with her greater cultural context. If she succeeds, she harmonizes her experience and the part coheres with the whole. Value, harmony, and stability ensue. Whitehead and Dewey describe our moral experience at a sufficient level of abstraction, one which could include the hosting of a dinner party or the conducting of an orchestra. Each part must cohere with the whole — harmony is the motivating ideal.

Much like Whitehead, Dewey gives us a processive account of reality which seems to cohere with personal experience; however, Dewey’s description of the pattern of inquiry has been accused of being so broad and vague that the Nazi resolution of the Jewish problem could be described according to it..33 The Germans under Hitler constituted their situation during the Great Depression as problematic. Their economy was in shambles, and their national pride was wounded. They found within their situation the constitutive elements, marginally-German, supposed conspirators and enemies of all sorts, to employ in resolving their situation. They achieved a sort of integration of their experience and a distorted sort of harmony in armament and invasion to reincorporate native Germans outside of their truncated borders. They consciously recruited aesthetic ideals and played on the national emotions of soil and blood. Thus, according to the Hitler-reductio, to condemn morally their actions with the language of Dewey or Whitehead is no easy task. The reductio causes moral philosophers to long for universality in any of its rationalist iterations.

The British Problem at the Intersection: The Remains of the Day

The philosophical depiction of aesthetic experience, of which moral dimensions compose a part, is problematic if individuals acting under aesthetic norms, guided by manners and in service of harmonizing part-whole relations, engage in outright immorality or shy away from moral duty in the face of evil. This is the “British” problem because to highlight it, we must attend to the British characters in The Remains of the Day. While much has been written on the film (and the Ishiguro novel upon which it is based), about the role of class and the symbolic nature of British imperial politics, the film also serves as an excellent test case for the continuity between aesthetics and ethics.34 The setting of The Remains of the Day, the aristocratic estate of Darlington Hall in rural England, announces an aesthetic emphasis on beauty and order which persists throughout the film. Most of the action in the film occurs in the pre-war 1930s, but the film flashes forward to the post-war 1950s to show “present” character interactions. The central characters are an emotionally-repressed butler, Mr. Stevens (Anthony Hopkins), his superior and owner of the estate in the 1930s, Lord Darlington (James Fox), and his fellow caretaker of the estate, Miss Kenton (Emma Thompson). The problematic relationship between aesthetic orientation and morality comes into view by focusing on Lord Darlington’s demeanor throughout the events of the 1930s, and Mr. Stevens’s comportment to the politically and morally problematic events that unfold at Darlington Hall.

Lord Darlington had a friend in Germany against whom he fought in the First World War, with whom he intended to sit down and have a drink after the war. But this never happened, as the German friend, ruined by the inflation that ensued in the post-Versailles Weimar Republic, took his own life. Lord Darlington exclaims to Mr. Stevens, “The Versailles Treaty made a liar out of me.” Darlington laments that the conditions of the treaty, (debt reparations, guilt clause) were too harsh: “Not how you treat a defeated foe,” as Darlington puts it. With this as his proximate motivation, Lord Darlington uses his influence to broker the policy of appeasementtoward Nazi Germany. It appears that Lord Darlington puts manners before moral duty. He hosts the delegates from Germany, France, and the United States at his home, and they dine dressed in black tie, served by the army of under-butlers commanded by Mr. Stevens.

One is tempted to view Lord Darlington’s behavior as kind, if not for other telling incidents. He temporarily agrees to employ two Jewish refugees at his estate, and it is made clear to the viewer that he understands the dangers they faced in Germany and that his home is serving as a sanctuary. However, after reading the work of Houston Stewart Chamberlain, Lord Darlington orders that two German, Jewish maids should be discharged, as he considers their employment inappropriate for his German guests. Mr. Stevens carries out the order without reflection, while Miss Kenton threatens to resign in protest, but fails to follow through out of self-admitted weakness.35 Thus, Darlington knew of the Nazi policies in Germany, understood the potential plight of the maids, but fired them anyway in service of behavior “appropriate” for his German guests.

Darlington’s elevation of manners above duty reappears as he cannot even tell his godson (Hugh Grant), whose father has died and who is soon to be married, about the birds and the bees. He asks Mr. Stevens, his butler, to do it for him. Darlington seems unwilling to confront the issue of sexuality as it offends his Victorian manners and sensibilities. Thus, manners, while they can be seen as the outward display of inner character, here get in the way of the more difficult, unmannerly, and inappropriate conduct commanded in the face of negotiation with the Germans, the employment of the Jewish maids, and the acceptance of surrogate fatherly duties.

Mr. Stevens’s motivations are more opaque to the audience. He is so univocally driven to serve and fulfill his duty to Lord Darlington, that he almost fails to portray any moral subjectivity.36 But as the head butler, his service is also for the aesthetic ideals of orderliness and cleanliness. The prospect of a dustpan being left on the landing frightens him, such that he rushes to retrieve it before his employer notices his shortcoming. Mr. Stevens’s single-minded focus is best displayed when his own father, also an employee, is dying. Stevens attends to the dinner of the foreign delegates without pain or pause, while his own father lies on his death bed. His relationship with Miss Kenton, central to the development of his character, reveals his coldness, emotional repression, and narrowly driven service toward aesthetic ends. Miss Kenton first extends kindness to Mr. Stevens by putting flowers in his office, but he asks that they be removed so as not to distract him. She falls in love with Mr. Stevens and ends up in tears when she tries to break through his emotional wall and communicate her love to him. But he ignores her and asks to be excused to attend to his duties. Before her eventual departure and engagement to another man, she insults Stevens out of manifest distress that he has never expressed any emotional interest in her, but he still remains unmoved. After his reunion with her in the 1950s, Stevens departs for Darlington Hall in a deluge of rain. Kenton cries, but Stevens, still fails to demonstrate any feeling and only raises his hat out of politeness. While Stevens’s class-based subordination could explain his failure to fulfill his duty to his father, his coldness to Miss Kenton illustrates that he was a cold rationalist in service of aesthetics — thinly defined aesthetics.

Reflecting on Mr. Stevens’s relationship to Miss Kenton reveals two sides of the problem at the intersection of aesthetics and ethics. First, because he serves only the aesthetic ideals of order, beauty, and cleanliness, he does a disservice to the human and intersubjective dimensions of moral experience. He is polite but inattentive and stoic in the face of obvious human suffering, from the firing of the Jewish maids, to the death of his father, to the jilted and regretful Miss Kenton. Does this pose a problem for the continuity between aesthetics and ethics? Stevens serves beauty at the cost of moral duty but also interpersonal sympathy. Since an emotional angle of vision is the necessary condition for attending to moral circumstances, his aesthetic orientation is too narrow. While he has an aesthetic ideal as his motive, he has a rational methodology to achieve it. He acts in each situation as if subsuming his particular action under the universal conceptual criteria of serving beauty and order. He does not allow his actions to flow from his feelings as Whitehead would prescribe. His contribution to others is his spirit, but this is a cold, deliberate, and rational spirit. Thus, with Mr. Stevens as a test case, a conception of aesthetic experience needs to be broad enough to include emotional comportment. Failing to do so through operating in service of a narrow ideal of beauty reveals an impoverished sense of aesthetics which results in immorality.

American Congressman, Mr. Lewis (Christopher Reeve) of The Remains of the Dayserves as a pivot to the American problem at the intersection of aesthetics and ethics discussed at length below. Laughed at as nouveau riche by the British delegates, Lewis attends the conference with the intent of resisting the policy of appeasement. Because he fails to recruit the French delegate, Dupont d’Ivry (Michael Lonsdale), to his side (D’Ivry is busy attending to his sore feet), Mr. Lewis resorts to making an impolite toast at the black tie dinner. He argues in favor of the Realpolitik of professionals, rather than that of “honorable amateurs,” which is his epithet for the noblemen in his company and the Lord who is his host. In his toast “to the professionals” he embodies the moral high ground against the Nazis and the unmannerly and barefooted behavior of a stereotypical American on aristocratic soil; thus he hammers in the wedge that separates manners from morals. Apparently, Americans stand up for right against wrong even at the expense of politeness and pretty conduct. Lewis is a representative character for those skeptical of continuity between aesthetics and ethics. He knows that aesthetic ideals, when reducible to the appreciation of good taste and mannerly behavior, can dull moral distinctions. Yet he fails to unify the precariousness of his situation in a manner which Whitehead or Dewey describe.

The American Problem at the Intersection: Taking Sides

Taking Sides tells the story of Dr. Wilhelm Furtwängler, (Stellan Skarsgård), one of the most respected German conductors of the 20th century, who chose to remain in Germany during the Nazi regime. After Germany’s defeat, he fell victim to a ruthless investigation by the Allies. The major in charge of the investigation is a stereotypically uncultured American, Major Steven Arnold (Harvey Keitel), who works in the insurance business. Arnold tries to uncover how complicit Furtwängler was. Furtwängler was appointed to the Privy Council, he was Hitler’s favorite conductor, and Goebbels and Goering honored him. However, he never joined the Nazi party, he helped numerous Jews escape, and several witnesses testify that he tried to protect Jewish musicians under his direction.

The audience is left to judge Furtwängler morally. On the one hand, Arnold has the moral high ground. The Nazis perpetrated the Holocaust, and the Allied victory ended it. Justice awaits the guilty. But Major Arnold is no Congressman Lewis, who has the outward appearance of a British Peer but falls short of their mannerly conduct only by degree. Arnold is a bullying interrogator, somewhere between the caricature of an ugly American and a down-to-earth pragmatist who thinks musical genius is no excuse for collusion with Nazism, and he is willing to employ an overbearing rudeness to expose this. For Arnold, the question is all about strength of will, and he deems Furtwängler weak. However, Arnold seems to misunderstand most of Furtwängler’s replies to his questions, and at times, his interrogation seems like self-righteous taunting and badgering. The viewer is left wondering whether the distressed conductor or the clinched-fist interrogator is acting more like a Nazi.

In one telling exchange, Furtwängler claims that art has mystical powers, which nurture man’s spiritual needs. He confesses to being extremely naïve. While having maintained the absolute separation of art and politics, he devoted his life to music because he thought through music he could do something practical: to maintain liberty, humanity, and justice. Arnold replies with sarcastic disdain, “Gee, that’s a thing of beauty. […] But you used the word “naïve.” Are you saying you were wrong in maintaining the separation of art and politics?”37 Furtwängler replies that he believed art and politics should be separated, but that they were not kept separate by the Nazis, and he learned this at his own cost. Furtwängler is in an obvious bind here. He cannot hold the following propositions together without internal contradiction: (1) Art has mystical power which nurture’s man’s spiritual needs; (2) Art and politics should be kept separate; (3) Art can maintain liberty, justice and humanity; (4) Art was not kept separate from politics during Nazi rule in Germany, and this was a bad thing. If art nurtures man’s spiritual needs, but art must be kept separate from politics, are man’s spiritual needs distinct from questions of community and well-functioning societies? Put otherwise, can music perform its practical function of maintaining justice, while being separate from politics? It would not seem so.

In what follows this interrogation, Arnold accuses Furtwängler of weakness, of selling out to the Nazis for ordinary petty reasons of fear, jealousy of other conductors, and selfishness. Arnold’s two subordinates are offended by his demeanor and his denigration of a national artistic genius and hero. His assistant eventually refuses to participate. She claims that Arnold is embodying the demeanor of the S.S., which she witnessed firsthand. But Arnold shows her a film of corpses being bulldozed into mass graves, and he tells her that Furtwängler’s friends did this, and by virtue of the fact that Furtwängler actually helped some Jews escape, he knew what they were doing.

The moment of supposed revelation for the viewers of the film comes by way of archival footage, in which Furtwängler is shown shaking hands with Nazi propaganda minister Joseph Goebbels after a concert. Furtwängler’s face reveals the complexity of emotions at work — placidness, fear, and contempt. Furtwängler wipes his hand on his leg, revealing his disdain for his patron, but remains reserved and inoffensive. At once the viewer feels he is redeemed, because his true feelings for Goebbels and the Nazi project are revealed, but Furtwängler’s weakness is evident, as Arnold would have pointed out. Ultimately Furtwängler served the harmonious sensibility of artistic creation. Indeed, throughout the film the German admiration of him is severe, especially when contrasted to Arnold’s unimpressed frankness with him. The German temperament and faithfulness to aesthetic appreciation is manifest in a scene where the German audience stands in the rain, listening to Furtwängler conduct a symphony. To leave would offend, and service to the aesthetic ideals cannot give way to pragmatic considerations — how “American” that would be! One imagines Arnold thinking “what insensible dolt stands in the rain to listen to music?” Perhaps Congressman Lewis’s willingness to offend at the black tie dinner can be seen as a middle ground between Arnold’s bullying and Furtwängler’s and Darlington’s inverted values. However, this might only translate conduct into class, hiding the one true moral question beneath another layer of social convention. Arnold would insist that knowing where your salad fork belongs may not prevent you from colluding with murderers.

The Continuity between Ethics and Aesthetics

For both Whitehead and Dewey there are no universal moral situations. Our occasions of experience are always contextual and specific, never occurring in vacuous actuality. But this calls for a more general approach to descriptive ethics, not a more particularized prescription of universal moral laws. Both philosophers begin with a description of the general traits of experience and each uses highly aesthetic language. Each treats imagination and vision, not rationality, as operative in navigating morally problematic situations. Whitehead, by making feeling a metaphysical category, gives emotion a primary role; Dewey, in collapsing the gap between scientific, practical, and moral inquiries, gives imaginative intelligence primacy.

Neither of our two films presents the ideal character, with an emotional comportment and an intensity of experience able to serve as the causally efficacious and morally demanding superject in its environment. Nor do they offer a character of superior imaginative intelligence who finds and applies the elements of her problematic situation as means toward the valuable integration of meaning. This is not a surprise. England appeased the Nazis; the Holocaust occurred and so did the very limited prosecution of the guilty by the Allies afterwards. Furthermore, ugly, but welcomed, Americans plodded onto European soil either on the model of Major Arnold, at worst, or on that of Congressman Lewis at best. (He eventually buys Darlington Hall and retains Mr. Stevens as his butler, but he installs a ping-pong table there, of all aesthetic affronts). Does the “American” problem recur in summer retreats to European museums and cafes? Americans plod, loud and entitled, over the artistic feats of the Continent, and their European hosts translate aesthetic missteps into moral offense.

Where did each character fall short, and what did their shortcomings reveal about the intersection of aesthetics and ethics? Lord Darlington employed his servants to erect a mannerly and orderly veneer between him and that which is ugly. However, he can be viewed as a tragic figure because his mild manners and sensitivity to common cultural (and aesthetic in the narrow sense) values with the Germans were used against him. He ended in disgrace as the news of his involvement in the appeasement was publicized by the press. But his heightened sense of manners disabled him from confronting the soil of moral problems as he did not want to get dirty — (that’s what the servants are for). The head butler, Stevens, was not the emotionally comported or spontaneously active character tacitly advocated for by Whiteheadian ethics, but the coldly rational and deliberative agent serving a narrow aesthetic end. Miss Kenton and Furtwängler demonstrated a weakness of will in the face of wrong-doing, and for that they are condemned, not by an aesthetic measure, but by a pragmatic one. Their beliefs were their propensities to act, and their inability to act revealed a weak belief in their moral ideals.38 But the American characters are not morally pure. As the victors, the

tools they had at their disposal to resolve their situations were ready at hand, and they too were constituted by their prehensions of their environment. Denigrating an artistic genius does not show the service of a moral ideal, but only the privileged position of Major Arnold of judging Furtwängler’s weakness from outside his context.

These films do illustrate the tension at work at the intersection of aesthetics and ethics. While both films depict the limitations and failures of the tendency to “aestheticize” morality, they do not prove the need to import a falsely universal moral ideal antecedent to the experience of a particular problematic situation in order to judge right from wrong. Insofar as the tools needed to make these judgments are had in experience, they have been, accurately described by figures like Whitehead and Dewey, in aesthetic language. The Reductio ad Hitlerum only succeeds if the meaning of aesthetics is deflated and reduced to something much narrower than either Whitehead or Dewey intended, such as reflection on artistic creation. The broad use of aesthetics advocated here does not fail to draw moral distinctions in the face of Nazi atrocities while blindly serving the ideal of artistic beauty or mere manners. Rather, as including imagination and emotion, an aesthetic orientation to ethics encompasses the problems posed by the characters’ shortcomings, even if their moral shortcomings run parallel to their heightened aesthetic and misguided sensibilities.


  1. Hans Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, (London: Continuum, 2006), 31. Nöel Carroll makes the further claim that because of Kant’s aesthetic theory and its interpretation, twentieth century philosophers have neglected the ethical criticism of art. (Noël Carroll, “Art and Ethical Criticism: An Overview of Recent Directions of Research,” Ethics, Vol. 110, No. 2 (January 2000), pp 350). ↩︎
  2. Thomas Alexander, “John Dewey and the Moral Imagination: Beyond Putnam and Rorty toward a Postmodern Ethics,” Transactions of the Charles Sanders Peirce Society, Vol. XXIX, No. 3, (Summer 1993), 373. ↩︎
  3. For a complex examination of this problematic, see George Kateb, “Aestheticism and Morality: Their Cooperation and Hostility,” Political Theory, Vol. 28, No. 1 (Feb., 2000), pp. 5-37. ↩︎
  4. See Noël Carroll, “Art and Ethical Criticism: An Overview of Recent Directions of Research,” Ethics, Vol. 110, No. 2 (January 2000), pp. 350-387. Carroll highlights the problematic relationship between ethics and art criticism by examining the immorality and aesthetic value of The Triumph of the Will, among other artifacts. ↩︎
  5. Boaz Neumann, “The National Socialist Politics of Life,” New German Critique, No. 85, Special Issue on Intellectuals (Winter, 2002), p 120. ↩︎
  6. Paul Betts, “The New Fascination with Fascism: The Case of Nazi Modernism,” Journal of Contemporary History, Vol. 37, No. 4 (Oct., 2002), 546. ↩︎
  7. Betts, “The New Fascination with Fascism,” 547. ↩︎
  8. Betts, “The New Fascination with Fascism,” 547. ↩︎
  9. Alfred North Whitehead, Process and Reality, (London: The Free Press, 1978), 18. ↩︎
  10. Whitehead, Process and Reality, 18, 22. ↩︎
  11. Whitehead, Process and Reality, 19. ↩︎
  12. Harold B. Dunkel, “Creativity and Education,” Educational Theory, Volume XI, Number 4, (1961), 209. ↩︎
  13. Whitehead, Process and Reality, 29. ↩︎
  14. John B. Cobb, “Whitehead’s Theory of Value,” religion-online.org Accessed 2/27/2015. ↩︎
  15. Cobb, “Whitehead’s Theory of Value.” ↩︎
  16. Whitehead, Process and Reality, 212. ↩︎
  17. Cobb, “Whitehead’s Theory of Value.” ↩︎
  18. Cobb, “Whitehead’s Theory of Value.” ↩︎
  19. Process and Reality, 222. ↩︎
  20. Cobb, “Whitehead’s Theory of Value.” ↩︎
  21. Cobb, “Whitehead’s Theory of Value.” ↩︎
  22. Cobb, “Whitehead’s Theory of Value.” ↩︎
  23. Dewey, Later Works Vol. 1, Ed. Boydston, (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1967-1990) 42-45. ↩︎
  24. Dewey, Logic The Theory of InquiryLW 12: 110. ↩︎
  25. Dewey, LW 12: 121. ↩︎
  26. James Gouinlock, John Dewey’s Philosophy of Value, (New York: Humanities Press, 1972), 132. ↩︎
  27. Dewey, LW 10: 143. ↩︎
  28. Dewey, LW 1: 9. ↩︎
  29. Gouinlock, John Dewey’s Philosophy of Value, 150. ↩︎
  30. Gouinlock, John Dewey’s Philosophy of Value, 151. ↩︎
  31. Gouinlock, John Dewey’s Philosophy of Value, 152. ↩︎
  32. Alexander, “John Dewey and the Moral Imagination,” 384. ↩︎
  33. Richard Posner*, Law, Pragmatism, and Democracy*, (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2003), p. 45. Posner claims that pragmatism, via Darwinism, has nurtured philosophies including Nazism. ↩︎
  34. See, for example, Meera Tamaya, “Ishiguro’s Remains of the Day: The Empire Strikes Back,” Modern Language Studies, Vol. 22, No. 2 (spring, 1992), pp. 45-56. Tanaya focuses on the relationship between Darlington and Stevens as one of colonizer and colonized, subject and object. ↩︎
  35. See Geoffrey G. Field, Evangelist of Race: The Germanic Vision of Houston Stewart Chamberlain, (New York: Columbia University Press, 1981). ↩︎
  36. See McCombe, “The End of (Anthony) Eden: Ishiguro’s “The Remains of the Day” and Midcentury Anglo-American Tensions,” 78. ↩︎
  37. See Page R. Laws, “Taking Sides by Ronald Harwood; India Ink by Tom Stoppard,” (review), Theatre Journal, Vol. 48, No. 1 (Mar., 1996), pp. 107-108. Laws makes note of the fact that the Nazis used art in the service of politics. ↩︎
  38. Charles Sanders Peirce, Collected Papers (1958-1966), Vol. 5, Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss, eds., (Cambridge: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press), 400. ↩︎

References: 

Alexander, Thomas. “John Dewey and the Moral Imagination: Beyond Putnam and Rorty toward a Postmodern Ethics.” Transactions of the Charles Sanders Peirce Society. Vol. XXIX. No. 3. (Summer 1993).

Betts, Paul. “The New Fascination with Fascism: The Case of Nazi Modernism.” Journal of Contemporary History, Vol. 37. No. 4. (Oct., 2002).

Carroll, Noël. “Art and Ethical Criticism: An Overview of Recent Directions of Research.” Ethics. Vol. 110, No. 2 (January 2000), pp. 350-387.

Cobb, John B. Jr. “Whitehead’s Theory of Value.” www.religion-online.org.

Dewey, John. Later Works Vol. 1, Ed. Boydston, Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1967-1990.

Dewey, John. Later Works Vol. 10. Ed. Boydston, Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1967-1990.

Dewey, John. Later Works Vol. 12. Ed. Boydston. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1967-1990.

Dunkel, Harold B. “Creativity and Education,” Educational Theory. Vol. XI. No. 4. (1961).

Field, Geoffrey G. Evangelist of Race: The Germanic Vision of Houston Stewart Chamberlain. New York: Columbia University Press, 1981.

Gadamer, Hans Georg. Truth and Method. London: Continuum, 2006.

Gouinlock, James. John Dewey’s Philosophy of Value. New York: Humanities Press, 1972.

Ivory, James. The Remains of the Day. Merchant Ivory Film, 1993.

Kateb, George. “Aestheticism and Morality: Their Cooperation and Hostility.” Political Theory. Vol. 28. No. 1 (Feb., 2000), pp. 5-37.

Neumann, Boaz. “The National Socialist Politics of Life.” New German Critique. No. 85. Special Issue on Intellectuals (Winter, 2002), pp. 107-130.

Peirce, Charles Sanders, (1958-1966) Collected papers. Vols. 1- 6, Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss, eds., (Cambridge: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press).

Posner, Richard. Law, Pragmatism, and Democracy, Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2003.

Szabó, István. Taking Sides. Paladin Production S.A., 2001.

Whitehead, Alfred North. Process and Reality. London: The Free Press, 1978.About the Author: 

Seth Vannatta earned his PhD in philosophy at Southern Illinois University Carbondale and is currently an Associate Professor in the Department of Philosophy and Religious Studies at Morgan State University, where he won the university award for research and scholarship in 2012. He studies the history of philosophy and American philosophy and is interested in philosophy’s relationship to other dimensions of culture including law, politics, education, and sport. He is the author of Conservationsim and Pragmatism in Law, Politics, and Ethics(Palgrave Macmillan, 2014) and editor and contributor to Chuck Klosterman and Philosophy: The Real and the Cereal (Open Court, 2012). He has published articles in The Pluralist, Contemporary Pragmatism, The European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy, Education and Culture, and others.

Notes on Ecological Aesthetics and Ethics

By David George Haskell

A sense of beauty is a rigorous, perhaps even objective, foundation for environmental ethics. Our human aesthetic judgment integrates many strands of experience: intellect, emotion, bodily senses, and all we know from our interactions with others, both human and non-human others. From this integration, we understand the good.

Of course, an aesthetic sense is subject to the whims of desire, passing fads, and superficial impressions. So a well-grounded ethic depends for its rigor on a mature sense of aesthetics. By “mature,” I mean a sense of aesthetics that emerges from many years of lived relationship with a place and its community of life, both human and non-human. Such experience allows us to “unself” our judgment into the wider experience of the community. Our aesthetic and then our ethic will thus emerge not just from the limited confines of our own self, but from the knowledge that lives within the networks from which communities are made.

Once we—collectively—have an integrated sense of aesthetics, we can begin to discern what is beautiful and what is broken about a place, and, from there, I believe we can begin to form an objective—or near-objective—foundation for ethical discernment. Answers emerge from the community of life itself, filtered through human experience and consciousness.

What do I mean by that? Years of experience in a particular place will open us to the lives of other people and other species in that place, so our sense of aesthetics will incorporate their realities. Once we have that, we have a ground for moving forward and making ethical decisions that are actually deeply rooted in the physical, biological realities of a place, rather than coming only from abstractions of a seminar room or dogmas in a philosophy born in another ecosystem.

Aesthetics is often presented as something that’s very subjective, divorced from the reality of the world. In fact, it’s the exact opposite. A sense of ecologic aesthetics comes from a very gritty, sensually rich experience that has its tendrils in the realities of a place.

None of this can answer the ethical nihilist who poses the question, “So, what? Ethics are vaporous illusions carved into the human nervous system by evolution.” But if some ground for ethics does exist in this universe, then a sense of aesthetics can, I think, help us find this ground by a process that fully acknowledges and embraces our existence as evolved members of ecological communities. This is a fully biological foundation for ethics.

On a practical level, if we try to answer questions about how to live in particular places without first listening to the realities and particularities of the place itself, our answers are going to be unmoored and will have terrible consequences. Understanding how to live ethically in a place is an extraordinarily complicated, important, and difficult challenge. Moving forward with answers that are not based on deep engagement with a place and its inhabitants is a recipe for disaster. So action in the world demands, first, a practice of listening.

Religious and philosophical traditions have known this for many millennia: contemplation and action go together, just as the inhale and the exhale go together. Monastic communities are deeply contemplative, but also have engaged in action in the world—whether that action is caring for other people in hospitals, or agricultural action, or caring for the sick. This history evinces the truth that we need open, contemplative spaces within our lives, especially lives of action. I think there’s a hunger for that kind of open space. Without it, we feel a desperation and a feeling that we’re up against the wall without a good way forward. Contemplative practices create spaces for new ideas, new connections to emerge. That sounds like a rather goal-oriented way of putting it, but I do think that one of the fruits of contemplation is an increased ability to come up with new ideas or to see old ideas in a new light.

In the environmental community, there are some instances of people making decisions about the fate of ecosystems when the decision-makers have never experienced the ecosystem at stake. When NGOs, governments, or businesses have decision-making structures that are divorced from the lived experience of a place, then the outcomes will most likely not be good for that place or the people in them. We need to bring lived experience of ecosystems back into the decision-making process.

Call: Aesthetics and Ethics in the Digital Age – British Society of Aesthetics Conference

Published: AUGUST 20, 2020

Call for Abstracts

British Society of Aesthetics: Aesthetics and Ethics in the Digital Age
27th and 28th May 2021
Cambridge, UK
https://fass.open.ac.uk/research/conferences/AEDA

Submission deadline: 31st December 2020

Submissions are invited for the upcoming conference British Society of Aesthetics: Aesthetics and Ethics in the Digital Age. The conference will take place on 27th and 28th May 2021 in Cambridge, UK.

The aim of this conference is to explore some developments in recent practice that raise new and interesting questions for the philosophy of art. Artists, working independently in different parts of the world, are creating new forms of technological interfaces and experimenting with the biological, the nano and the digital. At the heart of all their works is a deep ethos of balancing the aesthetic and the ethical in how we relate with others and our environment, whether in the same physical space or as distributed bodies. The spheres of the arts, sciences, and (in particular) technology overlap both to explore and to attempt to change the way in which we live in the world. These artistic practices raise questions about the interaction between aesthetics and ethics that go beyond those familiar to us in discussions over the past decade or so.

Abstracts of up to 1000 words should be submitted as an email attachment to Satinder Gill (spg12@cam.ac.uk) and Derek Matravers (derek.matravers@open.ac.uk). Please include the talk title, author’s name, affiliation and contact details in the body of email; and please write “BSA Conference Submission” in the subject line.  Abstracts should outline a talk lasting 25 minutes, on a topic related to the topic of the conference. The deadline for submissions is the end of 31st December 2020.

There will be no registration fee for the conference. UK-based contributing speakers will be encouraged to apply for the BSA Travel Stipend to cover travel and accommodation costs. The conference will adhere to BPA/SWIP Good Practice Scheme.

The conference website is https://fass.open.ac.uk/research/conferences/AEDA. For more information, please email Satinder Gill or Derek Matravers (emails above).

This conference is generously supported by the British Society of Aesthetics.

https://materialworldblog.com/2015/03/aesthetics-and-ethics-an-enquiry-into-their-relationship/

The relationship between aesthetics and ethics has long been the topic of scholarly debates, from Kant’s (1928[1790]) insistence that the experience of beauty involved disinterested contemplation and, subsequently, the separation of aesthetics from ethics, or Wittgenstein’s (1961[1889]) enigmatic proposition that ‘ethics and aesthetics are one’, to the numerous enquiries into the ethical aspects of art and art criticism or the aesthetic aspects of moral life and moral evaluation (e.g. Bourdieu 1984, Foucault 1985, 1986, Eco 1986, Eagleton 1990, Guattari 1995, Korsmeyer 1998, Levinson 2001, Rancière 2006, Osborne and Tanner 2007).
How has anthropology related to these debates? Thompson (2006[1973)], Bateson (2006[1973)], or Boone (1986), for example, in the tradition of a holistic anthropology, have analysed local concepts of beauty and illustrated the ways in which these concepts articulated with religious and moral values. Gell (1998), to give another example, through his notion of the artwork as an index, which enables the observer to make causal inferences about the artist’s intentions, has theoretically paved the way for inquiries into the morality of intentions. Furthermore, how can anthropology contribute to these debates, especially in light of its increasing interest in ethics (e.g. Lambek 2010, Faubion 2011, Robbins 2013, Keane 2013, 1014, Fassin and Lézé 2014, Laidlaw 2014)?

Participants have been invited to address the relationship between aesthetics and ethics in anthropology and to consider the following questions:
i) do the definitions of aesthetics and ethics currently in use in anthropology help or hinder us in our reflections on their relationship?
ii) when are the questions of aesthetics and ethics similar?
iii) what kind of theoretical framework is appropriate for reflecting on this relationship? (e.g. value theory; then the questions might be: how does aesthetic value relate to the notion of value generally? how does ethical value relate to the notion of value generally? are these types of value incompatible?)
iv) what kind of ethnographic topic is appropriate for reflecting on this relationship? (only those where there is an explicit expectation that aesthetic principles are guided by ethical considerations, such as Qur’anic art and Islamic fashion?)
v) should a third term, that is, politics, be also taken into consideration in order to better understand the relationship between aesthetics and ethics?

https://philpapers.org/browse/aesthetics-and-ethics

About this topic 

SummaryBroadly construed, Aesthetics and Ethics concerns the relationship between art and morality. Here we ask: Can artworks provide moral knowledge? Can artworks corrupt and instruct morally?  More narrowly construed, the category concerns the relationship between aesthetic and moral value. The chief question is this: Do moral flaws with works of art constitute aesthetics flaws? In addition, we can ask if aesthetic value is morally significant. This last issue has important implications for environmental ethics.
Key worksThe most important collection on the topic is Levinson 1998. The majority of the work on the topic is in essay form, but there are a few influential books. Gaut 2007 is an important, recent monograph. 
IntroductionsAlthough a bit out of date, Carroll 2000 provides an excellent overview of the area.  Gaut 2001 is also an excellent introduction.

References

Art and Ethical Criticism: An Overview of Recent Directions of Research.

Noël Carroll – 2000 – Ethics 110 (2):350-387.

Art and Ethics.

Berys Gaut – 2001 – In Berys Nigel Gaut & Dominic Lopes (eds.), 

The Routledge Companion to Aesthetics. Routledge. pp. 341–352.

Art, Emotion and Ethics.

Berys Gaut – 2007 – Oxford University Press.

Aesthetics and Ethics: Essays at the Intersection.

Jerrold Levinson (ed.) – 1998 – Cambridge University Press.

AESTHETICS & ETHICS: OTHERNESS AND MORAL IMAGINATION FROM ARISTOTLE TO LEVINAS AND FROM UNCLE TOM’S CABIN TO HOUSE MADE OF DAWN

In recent years, American Studies have taken a turn toward the political. However, although poststructuralism and deconstruction have undermined numerous of the moral-philosophical dogmas of the Western metaphysical tradition, many of the political claims that the revisionist turn in American Studies has voiced still rest, if tacitly, on these moral and ethical assumptions. As the latter often collide with the theoretical axioms that inform these revisionist works, some resort to what one could call the “pathos of marginality” and rather vague concepts of “otherness.” Moreover, these political-ideological readings often completely blot out aesthetic aspects, as these are suspected to be carriers of implicit and hegemonic strategies of representation.

In the first part, this study analyzes what role “otherness” plays in the most influential moral-philosophical approaches to date – from Aristotle and the Neo-Aristotelians (Alasdair MacIntyre, Martha Nussbaum) via Kantianism and its deconstructors (Jean-François Lyotard, J. Hillis Miller) to the works of Paul Ricoeur and Emmanuel Levinas – and sheds light on its highly problematic status in Western notions of justice. Moreover, on the background of these analyses it examines the role that aesthetics plays not only for, but within these approaches, with a special focus on what task literature is accorded to dramatize the clash of sameness and otherness.

Starting from a revised notion of the sublime, the second part “applies” the different approaches to four American novels: Harriet Beecher Stowe’s Uncle Tom’s Cabin, Herman Melville’s Billy Budd, Sailor, Richard Wright’s Native Son, and N. Scott Momaday’s House Made of Dawn, and examines how far the moral-philosophical systems carry to elucidate these texts. What becomes clear is that none of these works can be captured in their complexity by either one moral philosophy or one political agenda, in that every literary “exemplification” of such theory inevitably falls prey to the treacherous dynamics of the example – a dynamics that inhabits literature and haunts ethics, and that defies literature’s instrumentalization by either ethics or ideologies.

Keywords: American Studies, Aesthetics, Ethics, the Sublime, the Other, Otherness, Immanuel Kant, Jean-François Lyotard, J. Hillis Miller, Martha Nussbaum, Alasdair MacIntyre, Paul Ricoeur, Emmanuel Levinas, Harriet Beecher Stowe, Uncle Tom’s Cabin, Herman Melville, Billd Budd, Richard Wright, Native Son, N. Scott Momaday, House Made of Dawn, Ecology.

Contents

List of Abbreviations for Reference Works

Introduction

American Studies Today

Enter (And Leave): The Aesthetic

Difficult Neighbors: Ethics and Aesthetics

The Novels

I. The Kantian Legacy of Deconstruction

1. Kant – for Example

2. The Ethics of Reading and the End of History

2.1. Ce dangereux exemple…

2.2. De Man’s Demands

2.3. …close the gap!

2.4. Giving the Li(f)e to Miller’s Lie

3. Toward a Politics of the Sublime: Jean-François Lyotard

3.1. The Idea of the “Idea”

3.2. Lyotard Just Gaming?

3.3. The Sacrificial Sublime

II. The Return of Aristotle: Alasdair MacIntyre and Martha Nussbaum

4. Going Back Home: MacIntyre and the Greek Polis

4.1. The Price of Historicization

4.2. The Polis Rebuilt

4.3. Virtual Ethics and Virtuous Reading

4.4. Ethics, Practice, and the Narrative Unity of a Human Life

5. A Mind too Refined to be Touched by an Idea: Martha Nussbaum’s Aristotelian Liberalism

5.1. Aristotle and the Virtues

5.2. The Tragic Muse as Éducation Sentimentale

5.3. The End of Tragedy and The Limits of Identification

III. Approaching the Other: Emmanuel Levinas and Paul Ricoeur

6. Oneself for the Other: Emmanuel Levinas

6.1. Facing The Other

6.2. Ethics, Politics, and Literature

6.3. The Other Sublime

7. Oneself as Another: Paul Ricoeur

7.1. Toward a Narrative Ethics

7.2. Narration and Alterity

7.3. A Tragic Encounter – Narrating the Other

IV. Toward an Ethics of Literature

8. Harriet Beecher Stowe: Uncle Tom’s Cabin

8.1. How to Turn a Thing Into a Man, or: Categorical Imperative vs. Golden Rule

8.2. Sentimentalism as Aesthetic and Ethical Strategy

8.3. The Economy of Religion and Politics

8.4. Face/Off

9. Herman Melville: Billy Budd, Sailor

9.1. Phronimos Goes To War

9.2. Literature, Responsibility, and Political Philosophy: Hannah Arendt and Paul Ricoeur

9.3. (Ef-)facing the Other – Melville’s Silences, Ethics, and War

9.4. Singular Madnesses, Maddening Singularities: Vere, Billy, and the “Hebrew Prophets”

10. Richard Wright: Native Son

10.1. Polis into Metropolis, or: How to Identify with a Rat

10.2. Whose Narrative Is It, Anyway?

10.3. The Racial Sublime

10.4.  Re(w)ri(gh)ting Native Son, Or: Who’s Afraid of Bigger Thomas?

11. N. Scott Momaday: House Made Of Dawn

11.1.  Polis into Pueblo, or: How to Identify with a Bear

11.2. “Evil Was”: Balance, Control, and the Ethics of Myth

11.3. To Kill or Not to Kill

11.4.  Excursus: Is there an other Other? Toward an Environmental Ethics

Conclusion

References

Index of Names

My Related Posts

Aesthetics and Ethics: At the Intersection

On Aesthetics

On Beauty

Truth, Beauty, and Goodness: Integral Theory of Ken Wilber

Truth, Beauty, and Goodness

The Good, the True, and the Beautiful

On Classical Virtues

Indra’s Net: On Interconnectedness

Levels of Human Psychological Development in Integral Spiral Dynamics

Arts and Moral Philosophy

Human Rights and Human Development

Third and Higher Order Cybernetics

The Social Significance of Drama and Narrative Arts

Key Sources of Reserach

AESTHETICS AND ETHICS: THE STATE OF THE ART

Jeffory Dean

https://aesthetics-online.org/page/DeanState

Aesthetics and ethics

Tanner, Michael

https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/aesthetics-and-ethics/v-1

Aesthetics and Ethics: Essays at the Intersection

https://www.cambridge.org/core/books/aesthetics-and-ethics/44B8E5696692AEEEF09A034CFDE57B8C

Problems at the Intersection of Aesthetics and Ethics

Seth Vannatta (Morgan State University)

https://responsejournal.net/issue/2016-08/article/problems-intersection-aesthetics-and-ethics

‘ETHICS AND AESTHETICS ARE ONE’

Diané Collinson

The British Journal of Aesthetics, Volume 25, Issue 3, SUMMER 1985, Pages 266–272, https://doi.org/10.1093/bjaesthetics/25.3.266Published: 01 March 1985

Aesthetics and Ethics in Gadamer, Levinas, and Romanticism: Problems of Phronesis and Techne

David P. Haney

PMLA Vol. 114, No. 1, Special Topic: Ethics and Literary Study (Jan., 1999), pp. 32-45 (14 pages) Published By: Modern Language Association 

The Marriage of Aesthetics and Ethics

Series: Critical Studies in German Idealism, Volume: 15

Editor: Stéphane Symons

https://brill.com/view/title/31979

Ethics as Aesthetics: Foucault’S Critique of Moralization of Ethics

October 2019

Project: Ethics as Aesthetics: Foucault’s Critique of Moralization of Ethics

Erwin Arellano Mallo

University of Southern Mindanao

https://www.researchgate.net/publication/336242982_Ethics_as_Aesthetics_Foucault%27S_Critique_of_Moralization_of_Ethics

“One and the Same? Ethics, Aesthetics, and Truth.” 

Eaglestone, Robert.

Poetics Today 25, no. 4 (2004): 595-608. muse.jhu.edu/article/177238.

Notes on Ecological Aesthetics and Ethics

By David George Haskell

Aesthetics & Ethics: Otherness and Moral Imagination from Aristotle to Levinas and from Uncle Tom’s Cabin to House Made of Dawn

Thomas Claviez

Aesthetics & Ethics: Otherness and Moral Imagination from Aristotle to Levinas and from Uncle Tom’s Cabin to House Made of Dawn

(Heidelberg: Winter, 2008) 

http://www.claviez.de/?page_id=41

Wittgenstein’s Aesthetics

https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/wittgenstein-aesthetics/

Aesthetics and Ethics

Aesthetics and Ethics  

Richard Eldridge

The Oxford Handbook of Aesthetics

Edited by Jerrold Levinson

The Ethics of Aesthetics

Don Ritter Berlin, Germany

“Ethics and Aesthetics are One”: The Case of Zen Aesthetics

Bai, H. (1997).

Canadian Review of Art Education, 24(2), 37-52.

Ethics as Style:
Wittgenstein’s Aesthetic Ethics and Ethical Aesthetics

Kathrin Stengel

Independent Scholar, New York