The Fifth Corner of Four: Catuskoti in Buddhist Logic

The Fifth Corner of Four: Catuskoti in Buddhist Logic

Key Terms

  • Logic
  • Classical Logic
  • Non Classical Logic
  • Many Valued Logic
  • Multi Valued Logic
  • Three Valued Logic
  • Four Valued Logic
  • Catuskoti
  • Buddhist Logic
  • Lukasiewicz Logic
  • Kleene Logic
  • Intuitionistic Logic
  • Five Valued Logic

Researchers

  • Graham Priest
  • Kreutz, Adrian
  • Kapsner, Andreas
  • Jan Westerhoff
  • Hans Rudolf Kantor
  • Gunaratne, R. D.

The Fifth Corner of Four: An Essay on Buddhist Metaphysics and the Catuṣkoṭi

Source: The Fifth Corner of Four: An Essay on Buddhist Metaphysics and the Catuṣkoṭi. By Graham Priest. New York: Oxford University Press, 2018. / Matthew T. Kapstein

Source: The Fifth Corner of Four: An Essay on Buddhist Metaphysics and the Catuṣkoṭi. By Graham Priest. New York: Oxford University Press, 2018. / Matthew T. Kapstein

Source: The Fifth Corner of Four: An Essay on Buddhist Metaphysics and the Catuṣkoṭi. By Graham Priest. New York: Oxford University Press, 2018. / Matthew T. Kapstein

Source: The Fifth Corner of Four: An Essay on Buddhist Metaphysics and the Catuṣkoṭi. By Graham Priest. New York: Oxford University Press, 2018. / Matthew T. Kapstein

Source: The Fifth Corner of Four: An Essay on Buddhist Metaphysics and the Catuṣkoṭi. By Graham Priest. New York: Oxford University Press, 2018. / Matthew T. Kapstein

Source: The Fifth Corner of Four: An Essay on Buddhist Metaphysics and the Catuṣkoṭi. By Graham Priest. New York: Oxford University Press, 2018. / Matthew T. Kapstein

My Related Posts

You can search for these posts using Search Posts feature in the right sidebar.

  • Relation and Negation in Indian Philosophy
  • Hermann Weyl and L.E.J. Brouwer: Intuitive Continuum and Choice Sequences
  • Charles Sanders Peirce’s Visual Logic: Diagrams and Existential Graphs
  • Charles Sanders Peirce’s Theory of Signs
  • Semiotics and Systems

Key Sources of Research

“Understanding Nāgārjuna’s Catuṣkoṭi.” 

Gunaratne, R. D.

Philosophy East and West 36, no. 3 (1986): 213–34. https://doi.org/10.2307/1398772.

https://www.jstor.org/stable/1398772

“The Logical Form of Catuṣkoṭi: A New Solution.” 

Gunaratne, R. D.

Philosophy East and West 30, no. 2 (1980): 211–39. https://doi.org/10.2307/1398848.

https://www.jstor.org/stable/1398848

Na ̄ga ̄rjuna’s Logic

Aaron J. Cotnoir | aaron.cotnoir@uconn.edu| January 28, 2010

in G Priest , K Tanaka , Y Deguchi & J Garfield (eds) , The Moon Points Back . Oxford University Press . 2015

https://research-repository.st-andrews.ac.uk/handle/10023/11329

“The Catuskoti as a bilattice.”

Onishi, Takuro.

“Rationality, Argumentation and Embarrassment: A Study of Four Logical Alternatives (Catuṣkoṭi) in Buddhist Logic.” 

Bharadwaja, V. K.

Philosophy East and West 34, no. 3 (1984): 303–19. https://doi.org/10.2307/1398631.

https://www.jstor.org/stable/1398631

RECAPTURE, TRANSPARENCY, NEGATION AND A LOGIC FOR THE CATUSKOTI

Kreutz, Adrian (2019).

Comparative Philosophy 10 (1).

https://philpapers.org/rec/KRERTN-3

The recent literature on Nāgārjuna’s catuṣkoṭi centres around Jay Garfield’s and Graham Priest’s interpretation. It is an open discussion to what extent their interpretation is an adequate model of the logic for the catuskoti, and the Mūla-madhyamaka-kārikā. Priest and Garfield try to make sense of the contradictions within the catuskoti by appeal to a series of lattices – orderings of truth-values, supposed to model the path to enlightenment. They use Anderson & Belnaps’s framework of First Degree Entailment. Cotnoir has argued that the lattices of Priest and Garfield cannot ground the logic of the catuskoti. The concern is simple: on the one hand, FDE brings with it the failure of classical principles such as modus ponens. On the other hand, we frequently encounter Nāgārjuna using classical principles in other arguments in the MMK. There is a problem of validity. If FDE is Nāgārjuna’s logic of choice, he is facing what is commonly called the classical recapture problem: how to make sense of cases where classical principles like modus pones are valid? One cannot just add principles like modus pones as assumptions, because in the background paraconsistent logic this does not rule out their negations. In this essay, I shall explore and critically evaluate Cotnoir’s proposal. In detail, I shall reveal that his framework suffers collapse of the kotis. Taking Cotnoir’s concerns seriously, I shall suggest a formulation of the catuskoti in classical Boolean Algebra, extended by the notion of an external negation as an illocutionary act. I will focus on purely formal considerations, leaving doctrinal matters to the scholarly discourse – as far as this is possible.

On the relationship of Advaita Vedānta and Mādhyamika Buddhism

Reynolds, Eric T.

University of British Columbia
Date Issued. 1975

https://open.library.ubc.ca/media/stream/pdf/831/1.0093585/1

https://open.library.ubc.ca/soa/cIRcle/collections/ubctheses/831/items/1.0093585

Paradox and Negation in the Upanishads, Buddhism and the Advaita Vedanta of Sankaracarya (India)

Thompson, Heather.   California Institute of Integral Studies 

ProQuest Dissertations Publishing,  1982. 8400050.

This dissertation explores the uses of Paradox and Negation–in contrast and comparison–through the Upanishads and Buddhism to the Advaita Vedanta of Sankara. Paradox and Negation employed are not of ordinary parlance but are philosophic and dialectic tools indicating a state beyond the world of appearances–the Supreme.The Upanishads indicate the Supreme state by positing the Transcendent Atman–The Transcendent Subjectivity–and the Transcendent Brahman–the Transcendent Existentiality. In both aspects, the Supreme is seen as the antecedent state to the nest of appearances: Its existence supports all phenomena. By juxtaposing two apparently incongruous statements–thus producing a Paradox–the Upanishadic seers pushed the mind beyond its normal boundaries into a meditative insight. Similarly, through Negation, the seers denied the self-sustaining validity of phenomena.The Buddha, in contrast, forwarded a pragmatic’ philosophy, refusing to speculate about the existence or nature of the Supreme. Rather, he examined the conditions of daily life, their cause, their cessation and the route to their cessation. Passing through the nominalist teachers of the Hinayana school to the Mahayana school, a growing use of Paradox and Negation is seen and culminates in the dialectics of Nagarjuna. Nagarjuna pushed Paradox and Negation to extremes in his Catuskoti, four-fold argument, which revealed the logical inadequacies of all concepts. They have only causal or relational validity within the boundaries of the intellect. Outside that boundary, they have no self-nature or existence.Sankara, in his Advaita Vedanta, rising to another level on the spiral of Indian philosophy, takes from the teachings of the previous two traditions and elaborates and develops both. He recognizes that the phenomenal world has reality–but a temporary one. It exists only so long as the mind is held in sway by illusion and ignorance. Once the mind has been restored to its true state–which is a meditatively disciplined one–the phenomenal world is seen as having relative existence only and as totally dependent on the Supreme Brahman.The uses of Paradox and Negation by the three schools will be examined as contrasts and complements to each other.

“Who Understands the Four Alternatives of the Buddhist Texts?” 

Wayman, Alex.

Philosophy East and West 27, no. 1 (1977): 3–21. https://doi.org/10.2307/1397697.

https://www.jstor.org/stable/1397697

THE LOGIC OF THE CATUSKOTI 

GRAHAM PRIEST

Comparative Philosophy Volume 1, No. 2 (2010): 24-54 Open Access / ISSN 2151-6014 http://www.comparativephilosophy.org

CONTRADICTION AND RECURSION IN BUDDHIST PHILOSOPHY:
FROM CATUṢKOṬI TO KŌAN

Kreutz, Adrian (2019).

In Takeshi Morisato & Roman Pașca (eds.), Asian Philosophical Texts Vol. 1. Milano: Mimesis International. pp. 133-162.

https://philarchive.org/rec/KRECAR-2

Cutting Corners: A Critical Note on Priest’s Five-Valued Catuṣkoṭi.

Kapsner, Andreas (2020).

Comparative Philosophy 11 (2).

https://philpapers.org/rec/KAPCCA-3

https://scholarworks.sjsu.edu/comparativephilosophy/vol11/iss2/10/

The Fifth Corner Re-Examined: Reply to Priest

Andreas Kapsner January 24, 2022

“Don’t be so Fast with the Knife: A Reply to Kapsner,”

PRIEST, Graham (2020)

Comparative Philosophy: Vol. 11: Iss. 2, Article 11.
Available at: https://scholarworks.sjsu.edu/comparativephilosophy/vol11/iss2/11

The Fifth Corner of Four: An Essay on Buddhist Metaphysics and the Catuskoti.

Priest, Graham (2018).

Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.

https://philpapers.org/rec/PRITFC

Interpreting Interdependence in Fazang’s Metaphysics.

Jones, Nicholaos (2022).

Journal of East Asian Philosophy 2:35-52.

On Buddhist Logic

Adrian Kreutz

Thesis
MA by Research
University of Birmingham
Department of Philosophy

https://philpapers.org/rec/KREOBL

Abstract

This thesis is the attempt to find a logical model for, and trace the history of, the catuṣkoṭi as it developed in the Indo-Tibetan milieu and spread, via China, to Japan. After an introduction to the history and key-concepts of Buddhist philosophy, I will finish the first chapter with some methodological considerations about the general viability of comparative philosophy. Chapter §2 is devoted to a logical analysis of the catuṣkoṭi. Several attempts to model this fascinating piece of Buddhist philosophy with the tools of classical logic shall be debunked. A paraconsistent alternative will be discussed but eventually dismissed. As a rejoinder, I shall propose a model for the catuṣkoṭi with the help of speech-acts. The remainder of this chapter will look at Chinese and Japanese forms of the catuṣkoṭi which I shall model in a quasi-recursive system. The third and final chapter will look at the Kyoto School’s soku-hi dialectics which ties together the different threads of this essay. I will criticise an established, classical model of the soku-hi dialectics and offer an alternative with a second-order paraconsistent semantics.

Indian Logic

Wikipedia

https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Indian_logic

“The Logic of Four Alternatives.” 

Jayatilleke, K. N.

Philosophy East and West 17, no. 1/4 (1967): 69–83. https://doi.org/10.2307/1397046.

https://www.jstor.org/stable/1397046

A Russellian Analysis of Buddhist Catuskoti.

Jones, Nicholaos (2020).

Comparative Philosophy 11 (2):63-89.

https://scholarworks.sjsu.edu/comparativephilosophy/vol11/iss2/6/

The Catuskoti

by Peter Fumich

An essential principal to Buddhism is non-dualism. However, the Catuskoti is clearly a system still immersed in dualism. This sort of dualism is more like that of the dual in Tao. Taken by themselves, the two relative states contain within themselves the nature of the absolutes. The only thing which differentiates are the notions both, neither. It is much like the yin and yang symbol. However, more accurately as we go on we see a fractal emerge. Hence, the ultimate truth, one in which we seem to conceptually call the more subtle truth is an illusion. The infinite recursion of this extension hints at an ultimate truth arising at ¥. The conception which takes within it this very fractal nature is truly enlightened. A truth which is free from dualism is either entirely immersed within dualism, or it lacks the distinction of truth all together. The use of the Catuskoti serves the purpose to hint ultimately at a non-truth. Speaking in terms of tautologies and ineffables, we will see the Catuskoti is a conceptual elaboration of traditional dualism, absolute true and false. While this itself is a conceptual elaboration of the union of true and false, Sunyata or 0. Sunyata is a conceptual elaboration of itself, which of course cannot be explained conceptually because then it emerges from non-conceptual Sunyata to conceptual Sunyata of 0. We can hint at it by saying, as a truth space, the non-conceptual Sunyata be U, then the set of ineffables of U and tautologies of U forms the conceptual elaboration of U. It should be clear that careful attention to our use of V4, the Klein 4 group, will be sufficient to realize a conceptual grasp of the non-conceptual Sunyata. See http://jcer.com/index.php/jcj/article/view/420

https://jcer.com/index.php/jcj/article/view/420/445

https://11prompt.com/?q=node/491

Buddhist Logic and Quantum Dilemma

by Jayant Burde

ISBN: 9788120835528, 8120835522
Year of Publication: 2012
Binding: Hardcover
Edition: 1st

Paraconsistency and Dialetheism

Graham Priest

Handbook of the History of Logic

Volume 8, 2007, Pages 129-204

https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/abs/pii/S1874585707800069

The Many Valued and Nonmonotonic Turn in Logic

Graham Priest, in Handbook of the History of Logic, 2007

https://www.sciencedirect.com/topics/computer-science/valued-semantics

3.3 Contradiction in Eastern Philosophy

We have not finished with the Neoplatonist tradition yet, but before we continue with it, let us look at Eastern Philosophy, starting in India. Since very early times, the Law of Non-Contradiction has been orthodox in the West. This is not at all the case in India. The standard view, going back to before the Buddha (a rough contemporary of Aristotle) was that on any claim of substance there are four possibilities: that the view is true (and true only), that it is false (and false only), that it is neither true nor false, and that it is both true and false. This is called the catuskoti (four corners), or tetralemma.48Hence, the possibility of a contradiction was explicitly acknowledged. The difference between this view and the orthodox Western view is the same as that between the semantics of classical logic and the four-valued semantics for the relevant logic of First Degree Entailment (as we shall see). In classical logic, sentences have exactly one of the truth values T (true) and F (false). In First Degree Entailment they may have any combination of these values, including both and neither. Just to add complexity to the picture, some Buddhist philosopers argued that, for some issues, all or none of these four possibilities might hold. Thus, the major 2nd century Mahayana Buddhist philosopher Nāgārjuna is sometimes interpreted in one or other of these ways. Arguments of this kind, just to confuse matters, are also sometimes called catuskoti. Interpreting Nāgārjuna is a very difficult task, but it is possible to interpret him, as some commentators did, as claiming that these matters are simply ineffable.49

The Law of Non-Contradiction has certainly had its defenders in the East, though. It was endorsed, for example, by logicians in the Nyaayaa tradition. This influenced Buddhist philosophers, such as Darmakārti, and, via him, some Buddhist schools, such as the Tibetan Gelug-pa. Even in Tibet, though, many Buddhist schools, such as the Nyngma-pa, rejected the law, at least for ultimate truths.

Turning to Chinese philosophy, and specifically Taoism, one certainly finds utterances that look as though they violate the Law of Non-Contradiction. For example, in the Chuang Tzu (the second most important part of the Taoist canon), we find:50

That which makes things has no boundaries with things, but for things to have boundaries is what we mean by saying ‘the boundaries between things’. The boundaryless boundary is the boundary without a boundary.

A cause of these contradictions is not unlike that in Neoplatonism. In Taoism, there is an ultimate reality, Tao, which is the source and generator of everything else. As the Tao Te Ching puts it:51

The Tao gives birth to the One.

The One gives birth to the two.

The Two give birth to the three —

The Three give birth to every living thing.

It follows, as in the Western tradition, that there is nothing that can be said about it. As the Tao Te Ching puts it (ch. 1):

The Tao that can be talked about is not the true Tao.

The name that can be named is not the eternal name.

Everything in the universe comes out of Nothing.

Nothing — the nameless — is the beginning…

Yet in explaining this situation, we are forced to say things about it, as the above quotations demonstrate.

Chan (Zen) is a fusion of Mahayana Buddhism and Taoism. As might therefore be expected, the dialetheic aspects of the two metaphysics reinforce each other. Above all, then, Zen is a metaphysics where we find the writings of its exponents full of apparent contradictions. Thus, for example, the great Zen master Dōgen says:52

This having been confirmed as the Great Teacher’s saying, we should study immobile sitting and transmit it correctly: herein lies a thorough investigation of immobile sitting handed down in the Buddha-way. Although thoughts on the immobile state of sitting are not limited to a single person, Yüeh-shan’s saying is the very best. Namely: ‘thinking is not thinking’.

or:53

An ancient buddha said, ‘Mountains are mountains, waters are waters.’ These words do not mean that mountains are mountains; they mean that mountains are mountains. Therefore investigate mountains thoroughly…

Now interpreting all this, especially the Chinese and Japanese writings, is a hard and contentious matter. The writings are often epigrammatic and poetical. Certainly, the writings contain assertions of contradictions, but are we meant to take them literally? It might be thought not. One suggestion is that the contradictions are uttered for their perlocutionary effect: to shock the hearer into some reaction. Certainly, this sort of thing plays a role in Zen, but not in Mahayana Buddhism or Taoism. And even in Zen, contradictions occur in even the theoretical writings.

More plausibly, it may be suggested that the contradictions in question have to be interpreted in some non-literal way. For example, though ultimate reality is literally indescribable, what is said about it gives some metaphorical description of its nature. This won’t really work either, though. For the very reason that ultimate reality is indescribable is precisely because it is that which brings all beings into being; it can therefore be no being (and so to say anything about it is contradictory). At least this much of what is said about the Tao must be taken literally, or the whole picture falls apart.54

Indian Logic

https://tibetanbuddhistencyclopedia.com/en/index.php/Indian_logic

The Fifth Corner of Four: An Essay on Buddhist Metaphysics and the Catuṣkoṭi


Graham Priest, The Fifth Corner of Four: An Essay on Buddhist Metaphysics and the Catuṣkoṭi, Oxford University Press, 2018, 172pp., ISBN 9780198758716.

Reviewed by Mark Siderits, Seoul National University (Emeritus)
2019.05.18

https://ndpr.nd.edu/reviews/the-fifth-corner-of-four-an-essay-on-buddhist-metaphysics-and-the-catuskoti/

The Fifth Corner of Four: An Essay on Buddhist Metaphysics and the Catuṣkoṭi

Reviewed by Ronald S. Green

Journal of Buddhist Ethics
ISSN 1076-9005 http://blogs.dickinson.edu/buddhistethics Volume 27, 2020

Review of Graham Priest: The Fifth Corner of Four. An Essay on Buddhist
Metaphysics and the Catuṣkoṭi, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2018.

Mind, 2019, forthcoming.
Jan Westerhoff

https://ora.ox.ac.uk/objects/uuid:d8fa6404-3e65-4711-a7c9-e7c696e6602c/files/rb8515n415

https://ora.ox.ac.uk/objects/uuid:d8fa6404-3e65-4711-a7c9-e7c696e6602c

The Fifth Corner of Four: An Essay on Buddhist Metaphysics and the Catuṣkoṭi. By Graham Priest. New York: Oxford University Press, 2018. 208 pages.

Matthew T. Kapstein
École Pratique des Hautes Études, Paris, and the University of Chicago

Click to access 4-4-Kapstein-review.pdf

“Graham Priest, “The Fifth Corner of Four: An Essay on Buddhist Metaphysics and the Catuskoti.””.

Kreutz, A.

Philosophy in Review, Vol. 39, no. 3, Aug. 2019, pp. 146-8, https://journals.uvic.ca/index.php/pir/article/view/18802.

https://journals.uvic.ca/index.php/pir/article/view/18802

The Catuṣkoṭi, the Saptabhaṇgī, and “Non-Classical” Logic.

Priest, G. (2022).

In: Sarukkai, S., Chakraborty, M.K. (eds) Handbook of Logical Thought in India. Springer, New Delhi. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-81-322-2577-5_50

https://link.springer.com/referenceworkentry/10.1007/978-81-322-2577-5_50

References
  • Anderson, A.R., and N.D. Belnap. 1962. Tautological entailments. Philosophical Studies 13: 9–24.Article Google Scholar 
  • Anderson, A.R., and N.D. Belnap. 1975. Entailment: The logic of relevance and necessity. Vol. I. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar 
  • Battacharya, H.S, ed. and trans. 1967. Pramāṇa-naya-tattvālokālaṁkāra. Bombay: Jain Sahitya Vikas Mandal.Google Scholar 
  • Bharucha, F., and R.V. Kamat. 1984. Syādvāda theory of Jainism in terms of deviant logic. Indian Philosophical Quarterly 9: 181–187.Google Scholar 
  • Bochvar, D.A., and M. Bergmann. 1981. On a three-valued logical calculus and its application to the analysis of the paradoxes of the classical extended functional calculus. History and Philosophy of Logic 2: 87–112.Article Google Scholar 
  • Ganeri, J. 2002. Jaina logic and the philosophical basis of pluralism. History and Philosophy of Logic 23: 267–281.Article Google Scholar 
  • Garfield, J., trans. 1995. The fundamental wisdom of the middle way. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar 
  • Halldén, S. 1949. The logic of nonsense. Uppsala: A. B. Lundequistska Bokhandlen.Google Scholar 
  • Jayatilleke, K.N. 1963. Early Buddhist theories of knowledge. London: George Allen and Unwin.Google Scholar 
  • Kassor, C. 2013. Is Gorampa’s “freedom from conceptual proliferations” dialetheist? A response to Garfield, Priest, and Tillemans. Philosophy East and West 63: 399–410.Article Google Scholar 
  • Kleene, S.C. 1938. Notation for ordinal numbers. Journal of Symbolic Logic 3: 150–151.Article Google Scholar 
  • Kleene, S.C. 1952. Introduction to metamathematics. Amsterdam: North Holland Publishers.Google Scholar 
  • Koller, J.M., and P. Koller, eds. 1991. A sourcebook in Asian philosophy. Upper Saddle River: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar 
  • Marconi, D. 1979. La formalizzazione della dialettica. Turin: Rosenberg & Sellier.Google Scholar 
  • Matilal, B.K. 1981. The central philosophy of Jainism (Anekānta-Vāda). Ahmedabad: L. D. Institute of Indology.Google Scholar 
  • Ñāṇamoli, Bikkhu, and Bikkhu Bodhi, trans. 1995. The middle length discourses of the Buddha. Somerville: Wisdom Publications.Google Scholar 
  • Oppy, G. 2018. Ontological arguments. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Book Google Scholar 
  • Priest, G. 1979. Logic of paradox. Journal of Philosophical Logic 8: 219–214.Article Google Scholar 
  • Priest, G. 1995. Beyond the limits of thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 2nd edn, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002.Google Scholar 
  • Priest, G. 2008. Introduction to non-classical logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Book Google Scholar 
  • Priest, G. 2013. Nāgārjuna’s MūlamadhyakamakārikaTopoi 32: 129–134.Article Google Scholar 
  • Priest, G. 2014a. Plurivalent logic. Australasian Journal of Logic 11: 1. http://ojs.victoria.ac.nz/ajl/article/view/1830.Article Google Scholar 
  • Priest, G. 2014b. Speaking of the ineffable…. In Nothingness in Asian philosophy, ed. J. Lee and D. Berger. London: Routledge. Chapter 7.Google Scholar 
  • Priest, G. 2018. The fifth corner of four. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Book Google Scholar 
  • Priest, G. 2019. Natural deduction for systems in the FDE family. In New essays on Belnap-Dunn logic, ed. H. Omori and H. Wansing, 279–292. Berlin: Springer.Chapter Google Scholar 
  • Raju, P. 1954. The principle of four-cornered negation in Indian philosophy. Review of Metaphysics 7: 694–713.Google Scholar 
  • Sarkar, T. 1992. Some reflections on Jaina Anekāntavāda and SyādvadaJadavpur Journal of Philosophy 2: 13–38.Google Scholar 
  • Siderits, M., and Katsura, S., trans. 2013. Nāgārjuna’s middle way. Boston: Wisdom Publications.Google Scholar 
  • Stcherbatsky, F.T. 1962. Buddhist logic. New York: Dover Publications.Google Scholar 

None of the Above: The Catuṣkoṭi in Indian Buddhist Logic.

Priest, G. (2015).

In: Beziau, JY., Chakraborty, M., Dutta, S. (eds) New Directions in Paraconsistent Logic. Springer Proceedings in Mathematics & Statistics, vol 152. Springer, New Delhi. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-81-322-2719-9_24

https://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1007/978-81-322-2719-9_24?fromPaywallRec=true#citeas

References
  1. Deguchi, Y., Garfield, J., Priest, G.: The way of the dialetheist: contradictions in buddhism. Philos. East West 58, 395–402 (2008)Article Google Scholar 
  2. Garfield, J.: The Fundamental Principles of the Middle Way: Nāgārjuna’s Mūlamadhyamikakārikā. Oxford University Press, New York (1995)Google Scholar 
  3. Garfield, J., Priest, G.: Nāgārjuna and the limits of thought. Philos. East West 53, 1–21 (2003) (Reprinted as ch. 5 of Garfield’s, Empty Words. Oxford University Press, New York (2002) and as ch. 16 Priest (2002))Google Scholar 
  4. Garfield, J., Priest, G.: Mountains are Just Mountains (2009) (ch. 7 of D’Amato, M., Garfield, J., Tillemans, T. (eds.): Pointing at the Moon: Buddhism, Logic, Analytic Philosophy. Oxford University Press, New York)Google Scholar 
  5. Kassor, C.: Is Gorampa’s “Freedom from Conceptual Proliferations” dialetheist? A response to Garfield, Priest, and Tillemans. Philos. East West 63, 399–410 (2013)Article Google Scholar 
  6. Priest, G.: Hypercontradictions. Logique et Analyse 107, 237–243 (1984)MathSciNet Google Scholar 
  7. Priest, G.: Paraconsistent Logic. In: Gabbay, D., Guenther, D. (eds.) Handbook of Philosophical Logic, 2nd edn, Vol. 6, pp. 287–393. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht (2002)Google Scholar 
  8. Priest, G.: Beyond the Limits of Thought, 2nd edn. Oxford Unversity Press, Oxford (2002)Google Scholar 
  9. Priest, G.: The Limits of Language. In: Brown, K. (ed.) Encyclopedia of Language and Linguistics, 2nd edn, Vol. 7, pp. 156–159. Elsevier, Amsterdam (2005)Google Scholar 
  10. Priest, G.: Introduction to Non-Classical Logic: From If to Is. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2008)Google Scholar 
  11. Priest, G.: Jaina logic: a contemporary perspective. History Philos. Logic 29, 263–278 (2008)Google Scholar 
  12. Priest, G.: The logic of the Catuṣkoṭi. Comp. Philos. 1, 32–54 (2010)Google Scholar 
  13. Priest, G.: Plurivalent logic. Australas. J. Logic 11 (2014) article 1. http://ojs.victoria.ac.nz/ajl/article/view/1830
  14. Radhakrishnan, S., Moore, C. (eds.): A Source Book in Indian Philosophy. Princeton University Press, Princeton (1957)Google Scholar 
  15. Raju, P.: The principle of four-cornered negation in Indian philosophy. Rev. Metaphys. 7, 694–713 (1953)Google Scholar 
  16. Robinson, R.: Some logical aspects of Nāgārjuna’s system. Philos. East West 6, 291–308 (1956)Article Google Scholar 
  17. Ruegg, D.: The uses of the four positions of the Catuṣkoṭi and the problem of the description of reality in Mahāyāna buddhism. J. Indian Philos. 5, 1–71 (1977)Article Google Scholar 
  18. Scherbatsky, Th: Buddhist Logic, vol. 1. Matilal Banarsidass, Delhi (1993)Google Scholar 
  19. Thanissaro: Cula-Malunkyovada Sutta: the shorter instructions to Malunkya. http://www.accesstoinsight.org/tipitaka/mn/mn.063.than.html. Accessed Mar 2010
  20. Tillemans, T.: Is buddhist logic non-classical or deviant? Chap. 9 of Scripture, Logic, Language: Essays on Dharmakīrti and his Tibetan Successors. Wisdom Publications, Boston (1999)Google Scholar 

“Doxographical Appropriation of Nāgārjuna’s Catuṣkoṭi in Chinese Sanlun and Tiantai Thought” 

Kantor, Hans Rudolf. 2021.

Religions 12, no. 11: 912. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel12110912

https://www.mdpi.com/2077-1444/12/11/912

One Negation, Two Ways of Using It: Prasajyapratiṣedha in Bhāviveka and Candrakīrti’s Argumentation1

Chen Hsun-Mei
National Taiwan University / Kyoto University / Harvard Yenching Institute Wang Wen-Fang
Professor, National Yang Ming University

Nāgārjuna’s Tetralemma in Yamauchi Tokuryū’s Philosophy

Romaric Jannel

https://philarchive.org/archive/JANNTI

Three new genuine five-valued logics

Mauricio Osorio1 and Claudia Zepeda2
1 Universidad de las Am ́ericas-Puebla,
2 Benem ́erita Universidad Ato ́noma de Puebla {osoriomauri,czepedac}@gmail.com

https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S1571066120300888

Many-Valued Logic

SEP

https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logic-manyvalued/

Many-valued logics. A mathematical and computational introduction..

Augusto, Luis M. (2020).

London: College Publications.

https://philarchive.org/rec/AUGMLA

Many-valued logics are those logics that have more than the two classical truth values, to wit, true and false; in fact, they can have from three to infinitely many truth values. This property, together with truth-functionality, provides a powerful formalism to reason in settings where classical logic—as well as other non-classical logics—is of no avail. Indeed, originally motivated by philosophical concerns, these logics soon proved relevant for a plethora of applications ranging from switching theory to cognitive modeling, and they are today in more demand than ever, due to the realization that inconsistency and vagueness in knowledge bases and information processes are not only inevitable and acceptable, but also perhaps welcome. The main modern applications of (any) logic are to be found in the digital computer, and we thus require the practical knowledge how to computerize—which also means automate—decisions (i.e. reasoning) in many-valued logics. This, in turn, necessitates a mathematical foundation for these logics. This book provides both these mathematical foundation and practical knowledge in a rigorous, yet accessible, text, while at the same time situating these logics in the context of the satisfiability problem (SAT) and automated deduction. The main text is complemented with a large selection of exercises, a plus for the reader wishing to not only learn about, but also do something with, many-valued logics.

“Many-valued logic and its philosophy.” 

Malinowski, Grzegorz.

In The Many Valued and Nonmonotonic Turn in Logic (2007).

Improving the efficiency of using multivalued logic tools. 

Suleimenov, I.E., Vitulyova, Y.S., Kabdushev, S.B. et al. 

Sci Rep 13, 1108 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1038/s41598-023-28272-1

https://www.nature.com/articles/s41598-023-28272-1

Improving the efficiency of using multivalued logic tools: application of algebraic rings. 

Suleimenov, I.E., Vitulyova, Y.S., Kabdushev, S.B. et al. 

Sci Rep 13, 22021 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1038/s41598-023-49593-1

https://www.nature.com/articles/s41598-023-49593-1

An Introduction to Many-valued Logics

by Robert Ackermann

https://www.routledge.com/An-Introduction-to-Many-valued-Logics/Ackermann/p/book/9780367426040

“Foreword: Three-Valued Logics and Their Applications.” 

Cobreros, Pablo, Paul Égré, David Ripley, and Robert van Rooij.

Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 24, no. 1–2 (2014): 1–11. doi:10.1080/11663081.2014.909631.

https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/full/10.1080/11663081.2014.909631

The Two-Valued Iterative Systems of Mathematical Logic.

Post, Emil L.. 

(AM-5), Volume 5, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1942. https://doi.org/10.1515/9781400882366

Indian Modernity: Contradictions, Paradoxes and Possibilities

Author Avijit Pathak

Avijit Pathak is Professor at the Centre for the Study of Social Systems, Jawaharlal Nehru University, New Delhi.


Publisher Taylor & Francis, 2023
ISBN 1003830838, 9781003830832
Length 254 pages

Quintum Non-Datur‘, The Fifth Corner of Four: An Essay on Buddhist Metaphysics and the Catuskoti 

Priest, Graham, 

(Oxford, 2018; online edn, Oxford Academic, 20 Dec. 2018), https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198758716.003.0002, accessed 21 May 2024.

Levels of truth and reality in the philosophies of Descartes and samkara.

Schroeder, Craig (1985).

Philosophy East and West 35 (3):285-293.

https://doi.org/10.2307/1399157.

https://www.jstor.org/stable/1399157

https://www.proquest.com/openview/877c873a024f65b35ce731710fbca754/1?pq-origsite=gscholar&cbl=1820847

In the West, the general tendency of philosophers has been to understand things as being either real or unreal and to view propositions as either true or false. It is assumed that that which is real or true is opposite and exclusive of that which is unreal or untrue and that there can be no mediating ground. Only rarely does one find a philosopher who attempts to qualify truth and reality, that is, to hold that one thing might be, to some degree, more or less real than another, or to hold that one proposition could be more true than a second, while remaining less true than a third. On the contrary, philosophy in the West has generally been a quest to determine more clearly what is real and true and to contrast it more sharply with what is held to be unreal and untrue.

Often in this quest, however, philosophers display a tendency to qualify truth and reality even while trying to deny or exclude the possibility of such qualification. In Descartes’ writings, this qualification is set forth through his method of radical doubt as exercised in the Meditations. In his search for the real and the true, Descartes proceeds to doubt all of his former, commonsense beliefs. In this process, starting with that which is most easily doubted, that which seems the least ontologically and epistemologically well-grounded, he proceeds to submit to radical doubt beliefs of firmer and firmer ontological and epistemological footing, in search of something indubitable upon which to rebuild the structure of truth and reality. In spite of the fact that this method of radical doubt results in a reassertion of that which Descartes had more naively believed all along, it is instructive to compare the mediating levels observed by Descartes in his method to those of a non-Western philosopher who admits to qualified levels of truth and reality. Thus, while Descartes’ conclusions follow the more general Western pattern of drawing strict lines of demarcation between reality and nonreality, truth and untruth, we will concentrate more on his method, which stratifies and qualifies reality and truth prior to the drawing of these lines. Qualified levels of truth and reality are less of a problem for Indian philosophers. While India, too, has its schools of philosophy which admit to only two ontological or epistemological possibilities, one also finds in other schools a very careful and deliberate grading of reality and truth from levels of varying qualification to a level of ultimacy. Samkara’s Advaita Vedanta is one such school, and it is Samkara that will be considered in a comparison with Descartes. There are, strictly speaking, only one level of full truth and reality and one level· of full untruth and nonreality for Samkara. These extremes, however, are mediated by at least two other levels which are sadasadvilaksana,” other than real and unreal.” The reality or nonreality of these middle levels can only be understood in relation to the highest and lowest levels of reality. This ambiguity in their nature renders them anirvacanTya,” that about which we cannot speak.” For Samkara, there are only two sorts of things which are fully unreal,(1) the

The Problem of Two Truths in Buddhism and Vedānta

Author G.M.C. Sprung
Edition illustrated
Publisher Springer Science & Business Media, 2012
ISBN 9401025827, 9789401025829
Length 132 pages

The Uses of the Four Positions of the “Catus-koti” and the Problem of the Description of Reality in Mahayana Buddhism

RUEGG, D SEYFORT.  

Journal of Indian Philosophy; Dordrecht, Holland Vol. 5,  (Jan 1, 1977): 1.

https://www.jstor.org/stable/23438780

Four Corners—East and West.

Priest, G. (2011).

In: Banerjee, M., Seth, A. (eds) Logic and Its Applications. ICLA 2011. Lecture Notes in Computer Science(), vol 6521. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-18026-2_2

https://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1007/978-3-642-18026-2_2

References
  1. Garfield, J.: The Fundamental Principles of the Middle Way: Nāgārjuna’s Mūlamadhyamikakārikā. Oxford University Press, New York (1995)Google Scholar 
  2. Garfield, J., Priest, G.: Nāgārjuna and the Limits of Thought. Philosophy East and West 53, 1–21 (2003); reprinted as Priest, G.: Beyond the Limits of Thought, 2nd (extended) edn., ch.16. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2002)Article Google Scholar 
  3. Garfield, J., Priest, G.: Mountains are Just Mountains. In: D’Amato, M., Garfield, J., Tillemans, T. (eds.) Pointing at the Moon: Buddhism, Logic, Analytic Philosophy, ch. 7. Oxford University Press, New York (2009)Chapter Google Scholar 
  4. Priest, G.: Hypercontradictions. Logique et Analyse 107, 237–243 (1984)Google Scholar 
  5. Priest, G.: Paraconsistent Logic. In: Gabbay, D., Guenther, D. (eds.) Handbook of Philosophical Logic, 2nd edn., vol. 6, pp. 287–393. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht (2002)Chapter Google Scholar 
  6. Priest, G.: Introduction to Non-Classical Logic: from If to Is. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2008)Book MATH Google Scholar 
  7. Priest, G.: The Logic of the Catukoi. Comparative Philosophy 1, 32–54 (2010)Google Scholar 
  8. Raju, P.: The Principle of Four-Cornered Negation in Indian Philosophy. Review of Metaphysics 7, 694–713 (1953)Google Scholar 
  9. Ruegg, D.: The Uses of the Four Positions of the Catukoi and the Problem of the Description of Reality in Mahāyāna Buddhism. Journal of Indian Philosophy 5, 1–71 (1977)Article Google Scholar 
  10. Scherbatsky, T.: Buddhist Logic, vol. 1. Matilal Banarsidass, Delhi (1993)Google Scholar 
  11. Tillemans, T.: Is Buddhist Logic Non-classical or Deviant? In: Scripture, Logic, Language: Essays on Dharmakīrti and his Tibetan Successors, ch. 9. Wisdom Publications, Boston (1999)Google Scholar 
  12. Westerhoff, J.: Nāgārjuna’s Metaphysics: a Philosophical Introduction. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2010)Google Scholar

“The Avyākatāni and the Catuṣkoṭi Form in the Pāli Sutta Piṭaka, 2.” 

Rigopoulos, Antonio.

East and West 43, no. 1/4 (1993): 115–40.

Published By: ISMEO (International Association for Mediterranean and Oriental Studies)

http://www.jstor.org/stable/29757086.

“THE ARGUMENTS OF NĀGĀRJUNA IN THE LIGHT OF MODERN LOGIC.”

YU-KWAN, NG.

 Journal of Indian Philosophy 15, no. 4 (1987): 363–84.

http://www.jstor.org/stable/23445484.

“SOME LOGICAL ISSUES IN MADHYAMAKA THOUGHT.” 

GALLOWAY, BRIAN.

Journal of Indian Philosophy 17, no. 1 (1989): 1–35.

http://www.jstor.org/stable/23445510.

“NĀGĀRJUNA’S ‘CATUṢKOṬI.’” 

WESTERHOFF, J.

Journal of Indian Philosophy 34, no. 4 (2006): 367–95. http://www.jstor.org/stable/23497268.

“RATIONALITY IN EARLY BUDDHIST FOUR FOLD LOGIC.” 

HOFFMAN, F. J.

Journal of Indian Philosophy 10, no. 4 (1982): 309–37. http://www.jstor.org/stable/23445371.

On Garfield and Priest’s interpretation of the use of the catuskoti in Mūlamadhyamakakārikā

Wang, C., & Wen-fang, W. (2024).

Asian Philosophy, 1–21. https://doi.org/10.1080/09552367.2024.2309769

https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/abs/10.1080/09552367.2024.2309769

References
  • Austin, J. L. (1962). How to do things with words. Oxford University Press. 
  • Beall, J. (2009). Spandrels of truth. Clarendon Press. Google Scholar
  • Belnap, N. D. (1977). A useful four-valued logic. In J. M. Dunn & G. Epstein (Eds.), Modern uses of multiple-valued logics(pp. 8–37). Reidel. Google Scholar
  • Chen, H. M., & Wang, W. F. (2020). One negation, two ways of using it: Prasajyapratiedha in Bh¯aviveka and Candrak¯ırti’s argumentation. Tetsugaku, 4, 185–206. https://philosophy-japan.org/wpdata/wp-content/uploads/2020/06/Chen-Hsun-Mei-National-Taiwan-University-Kyoto-University-Harvard-Yenching-Institute-Wang-Wen-Fang-2020.pdfGoogle Scholar
  • Cotnoir, A. J. (2015). N¯ag¯arjuna’s logic. In T. Koji, Y. Deguchi, J. Garfield, & P. Graham (Eds.), The moon points back (pp. 176–188). Oxford University Press. Google Scholar
  • Davidson, D. (1984). Inquiries into truth and interpretation. Clarendon Press. Google Scholar
  • Field, H. (2008). Saving truth from paradox. Oxford University Press. Google Scholar
  • Frege, G. (1892). On Sense and Reference. In P. Geach & M. Black (Eds.), Translation from the philosophical writings of Gottlob Frege (pp. 56–78). Blackwell, 1952 . Google Scholar
  • Garfield, J. L. (1995). The fundamental wisdom of the middle way: N¯ag¯arjuna’s Mu¯lamadhyamakak¯arik¯a. Oxford University Press. Google Scholar
  • Garfield, J. L., & Priest, G. (2002). N¯ag¯arjuna and the limits of thought. In J. Garfield (Ed.), Empty words (pp. 86–108). Oxford University Press. Google Scholar
  • Garfield, J. L., & Priest, G. (2009). Mountains are just mountains. In M. D’amato, J. L. Garfield, & T. J. F. Tillemans (Eds.), Pointing at the moon – Buddhism, logic, analytic philosophy (pp. 71–82). Oxford University Press. Google Scholar
  • Kripke, S. (1975). Outline of a theory of truth. The journal of philosophy72(19), 690–716. https://doi.org/10.2307/2024634 Web of Science ®Google Scholar
  • Matilal, B. K. (2005). Epistemology, logic, and grammar in Indian philosophical analysis. Oxford University press. Google Scholar
  • Priest, G. (2006). In contradiction: A study of the transconsistent. Oxford University Press. Google Scholar
  • Priest, G. (2010). The logic of the catuskoti. Comparative philosophy1(2), 24–54. https://doi.org/10.31979/2151-6014(2010).010206 Google Scholar
  • Priest, G. (2018). The fifth corner of four: An essay on Buddhist metaphysics and the catuskoti. Oxford University Press. Google Scholar
  • Restall, R. (2005). Multiple conclusions. In Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science: Proceedings of the 12th International Congress, Oviedo (pp. 189–206). Kings College Publications. Google Scholar
  • Rumfitt, I. (2017). The liar without truth. In B. Armour-Garb (Ed.), Reflections on the liar (pp. 191–211). Oxford University Press. Google Scholar
  • Sider, T. (2007). Logic for philosophy. Oxford University Press. Google Scholar
  • Westerhoff, J. (2009). Nāgārjuna’s Madhyamaka – a philosophical introduction. Oxford University Press. Google Scholar
  • Whitehead, A. N., & Russell, B. (1962). Principia mathematica. Cambridge University Press. Google Scholar

The Deconstructionist Interpretation of Nagarjuna’s Catuskoti∗

Shi, Ruyuan (Chien-Yuan Hsu) PhD candidate, the Dep. of Religious Studies, the University of Calgary, Canada Sessional instructor, Mount Royal University, Canada

“INTRODUCTION: BUDDHISM AND CONTRADICTION.” 

Tanaka, Koji.

Philosophy East and West 63, no. 3 (2013): 315–21. http://www.jstor.org/stable/43285829.

“DOES A TABLE HAVE BUDDHA-NATURE?” 

Siderits, Mark.

Philosophy East and West 63, no. 3 (2013): 373–86. http://www.jstor.org/stable/43285836.

Buddhist Formal Logic, Part 1

Richard See Yee Chi

Edition reprint
Publisher Motilal Banarsidass Publ., 1984
ISBN 8120807308, 9788120807303
Length 304 pages

Reviewed Work: Buddhist Formal Logic

Richard S. Y. Chi

Review by: Douglas Dunsmore Daye
Philosophy East and West
Vol. 23, No. 4 (Oct., 1973), pp. 525-535 (11 pages)
Published By: University of Hawai’i Press

https://doi.org/10.2307/1397722.

https://www.jstor.org/stable/1397722

“The catuskoti: historical origins and modern interpretations.” (2021).

Alam Nizar, Syed Moynul.

“THE MĀDHYAMIKA ‘CATUṢKOṬI’ OR TETRALEMMA.” 

CHAKRAVARTI, SITANSU S., and SITANSU S. CHAKRABARTI.

Journal of Indian Philosophy 8, no. 3 (1980): 303–6. http://www.jstor.org/stable/23440331.

Early Buddhist Theory of Knowledge 

By K N Jayatilleke

Edition 1st Edition First Published 1963

eBook Published 15 August 2013

Pub. Location London Imprint Routledge

DOI https://doi.org/10.4324/9781315888347 

Pages 524

eBook ISBN 9781315888347

https://www.taylorfrancis.com/books/mono/10.4324/9781315888347/early-buddhist-theory-knowledge-jayatilleke

“Mysticism and Logic in Seng-Chao’s Thought.” 

Robinson, Richard H.

Philosophy East and West 8, no. 3/4 (1958): 99–120. https://doi.org/10.2307/1397446.

https://www.jstor.org/stable/1397446

“The Four Levels of Pratītyasamutpāda According to the Fa-hua hsüan i.” 

Bielefeldt, Carl.

Journal of the International Association of Buddhist Studies (1988): 7-29.

Nothingness in Asian philosophy.

Liu, JeeLoo, and Douglas L. Berger, eds. 

New York: Routledge, 2014.

“CONTRADICTIONS IN DŌGEN.” 

Tanaka, Koji.

Philosophy East and West 63, no. 3 (2013): 322–34. http://www.jstor.org/stable/43285830.

Emptiness, negation, and skepticism in Nāgārjuna and Sengzhao. 

Nelson, E. S. (2023).

Asian Philosophy33(2), 125–144. https://doi.org/10.1080/09552367.2023.2179966

https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/abs/10.1080/09552367.2023.2179966

Some General Remarks on Negation and Paradox in Chinese Logic

Author:  Klaus Butzenberger

Journal of Chinese philosophy 20, no. 3 (1993): 313-347.

Nagarjuna’s Madhyamaka: A Philosophical Introduction

Author Jan Westerhoff
Publisher Oxford University Press, 2009
ISBN 0199705119, 9780199705115
Length 256 pages

Izutsu’s Zen Metaphysics of I-Consciousness vis-à-vis Cartesian Cogito

Takaharu Oda
2020, Comparative Philosophy

Issue: 2
Volume: 11
Page Numbers: 90-112
Publication Date: 2020
Publication Name: Comparative Philosophy

https://doi.org/10.31979/2151-6014(2020).110207

https://www.academia.edu/43756980/Izutsu_s_Zen_Metaphysics_of_I_Consciousness_vis_à_vis_Cartesian_Cogito

What Can’t be Said: Paradox and Contradiction in East Asian Thought

Authors Yasuo Deguchi, Jay L. Garfield, Graham Priest, Robert H. Sharf
Publisher Oxford University Press, 2021
ISBN 0197526209, 9780197526200
Length 256 pages

Kalidas Bhattacharyya: Alternative Standpoints in Philosophy

Kalidas Bhattacharyya: Alternative Standpoints in Philosophy

Key Terms

  • Subjectivity
  • Intersubjectivity
  • Logic of Alternation
  • Logic of Disjunction
  • Three Absolutes
  • Alternative Standpoints
  • Tri Lok
  • Shiv Lok, Vishnu Lok, Brahma Lok
  • Double Negation
  • Triple Negation
  • Quadruple Negation
  • Relation and Negation

Researchers

  • Daya Krishna
  • Krishna Chandra Bhattacharyya
  • Kalidas Bhattacharyya
  • Gopinath Bhattacharyya

Kalidas Bhattacharyya: Alternative Standpoints in Philosophy

Source: Contemporary Vedanta Philosophy I

Source: Contemporary Vedanta Philosophy I

Source: Contemporary Vedanta Philosophy I

Source: Contemporary Vedanta Philosophy I

Source: Contemporary Vedanta Philosophy I

Source: Contemporary Vedanta Philosophy I

Source: Contemporary Vedanta Philosophy I

Source: Contemporary Vedanta Philosophy I

Kalidas Bhattacharya’s Notion of Swing in Standpoints

Source: Kalidas Bhattacharya’s Notion of Swing in Standpoints

Source: Kalidas Bhattacharya’s Notion of Swing in Standpoints

Kalidas Bhattacharyya and the logic of Alternation

Source: Kalidas Bhattacharyya and the logic of Alternation

Source: Kalidas Bhattacharyya and the logic of Alternation

Source: Kalidas Bhattacharyya and the logic of Alternation

Source: Kalidas Bhattacharyya and the logic of Alternation

Source: Kalidas Bhattacharyya and the logic of Alternation

Source: Kalidas Bhattacharyya and the logic of Alternation

Source: Kalidas Bhattacharyya and the logic of Alternation

Source: Kalidas Bhattacharyya and the logic of Alternation

Source: Kalidas Bhattacharyya and the logic of Alternation

Source: Kalidas Bhattacharyya and the logic of Alternation

Source: Kalidas Bhattacharyya and the logic of Alternation

Source: Kalidas Bhattacharyya and the logic of Alternation

Source: Kalidas Bhattacharyya and the logic of Alternation

Source: Kalidas Bhattacharyya and the logic of Alternation

My Related Posts

You can search for these posts using Search Posts feature in the right sidebar.

  • Relational Consciousness: Subjectivity and Otherness
  • The Spiritual Significance of Vedanta
  • Layers of Subjectivity
  • The Concept of the Absolute and Its Alternative Forms
  • Brahman: Absolute Consciousness in Advait (Non Dual) Vedanta Philosophy
  • Transcendental Self in Kant and Shankara
  • Ether in Kant and Akasa in Prasastapada: Philosophy in comparative perspective
  • God, Space and Nature
  • Purush – The Cosmic Man
  • The Transcendental Self
  • Truth, Beauty, and Goodness
  • Truth, Beauty, and Goodness: Integral Theory of Ken Wilber
  • The Aesthetics of Charles Sanders Peirce
  • Third and Higher Order Cybernetics
  • The Good, the True, and the Beautiful 
  • Cyber-Semiotics: Why Information is not enough
  • Meta Integral Theories: Integral Theory, Critical Realism, and Complex Thought 
  • From Individual to Collective Intentionality
  • Individual Self, Relational Self, and Collective Self
  • Individual, Relational, and Collective Reflexivity
  • Phenomenology and Symbolic Interactionism
  • Self and Other: Subjectivity and Intersubjectivity
  • Semiotics and Systems
  • Process Physics, Process Philosophy
  • Intersubjectivity in Buddhism
  • Lifeworld, System, and Intersubjectivity: Jurgen Habermas’ Communication Theory of Society
  • Levels of Human Psychological Development in Integral Spiral Dynamics
  • Phenomenological Sociology
  • Charles Sanders Peirce’s Continuum
  • The Great Chain of Being
  • On Holons and Holarchy
  • Networks and Hierarchies
  • Boundaries and Networks
  • Boundaries and Relational Sociology
  • A Calculus for Self Reference, Autopoiesis, and Indications
  • KNOT THEORY AND RECURSION: LOUIS H. KAUFFMAN

Key Sources of Research

The Philosophy of Kalidas Bhattacharyya

Daya Krishna $e Editor
Publication Language English
Publisher Name I.P.Q.Publication
Publication Place Pune
Publication Year 1985
No. of Pages 260

Alternative Standpoints in Philosophy: An Enquiry Into the Fundamentals of Philosophy

Author Kalidas Bhattacharya
Publisher Das Gupta, 1953
Original from the University of Michigan
Digitized Aug 31, 2007
Length 366 pages

On the concepts of relation and negation in Indian philosophy

by Kalidas Bhattacharya (Author)

(Calcutta Sanskrit College research series ; no. 109) 

Unknown Binding – January 1, 1977

Presuppositions of science and philosophy & other essays

by Kalidas Bhattacharya (Author)

Unknown Binding – January 1, 1974

Alternative standpoints: a tribute to Kalidas Bhattacharyya.

Bhattacharya, Kalidas & Chattopadhyay, Madhumita (eds.) (2015).

New Delhi: Suryodaya Books.

The anthology Alternative Standpoints: A Tribute to Kalidas Bhattacharyya is a tribute to Prof. Kalidas Bhattacharyya, the eminent thinker of twentieth-century India, on his birth centenary by his students. A distinguished philosopher and an academician, Prof. Bhattacharyya presented philosophy in an original way with scientific spirit. He was essentially a metaphysician and his metaphysics was deeply rooted in the traditions of Advaita Vedanta and Shaivism. His ultimate concern was to present a theory of freedom and a theory of the possibility of realizing that freedom. In this collection eminent scholars have written on different aspects of his philosophy. This anthology is divided into four parts – the first one concentrating on his metaphysics, the second part dealing with his views on freedom, the third one with education and science and the fourth one is a reminiscence of his student and his family members. In short this anthology tries to present a picture of Kalidas Bhattacharyya as a philosopher and also as a man within the two covers. This volume is expected to familiarize students and present-day philosophers the persona of Prof. Bhattacharyya and his philosophical positioning and pedagogical skillset.

Kalidas Bhattacharya’s Notion of Swing in Standpoints

Jigmey Dorje Lama
Research Scholar, Department of Philosophy & Comparative Religion, Visva- Bharati, Santiniketan

Volume : 6 | Issue : 12 | December : 2016 | ISSN – 2249-555X

Kalidas Bhattacharyya. New Perspectives in Indian Philosophy 

[Ed. Nirmalya Narayan Chakraborty].

The Ramakrishna Mission Institute of Culture, 2023.

Freedom, Transcendence, and Identity: Essays in Memory of Professor Kalidas Bhattacharyya

Editor Pradip Kumar Sengupta
Contributors Kalidas Bhattacharya, Indian Council of Philosophical Research
Publisher Motilal Banarsidass Publishe, 1988
ISBN 8120805283, 9788120805286

Contemporary Vedanta Philosophy I

George Burch

Contemporary Vedanta Philosophy II

George Burch

Contemporary Vedanta Philosophy Continued

George Burch

Kalidas Bhattacharyya and the logic of Alternation

Daya Krishna

Click to access 3-2-4.pdf

Three Absolutes and Four Types of Negation
Integrating Krishnachandra Bhattacharyya’s Insights?

By Stephen Kaplan
Book
The Making of Contemporary Indian Philosophy
Edition 1st Edition
First Published 2023
Imprint Routledge
Pages 14
eBook ISBN 9781003153320

Study on Four Logical Alternatives (catuṣkoṭi and catuṣkoṭi-vinirmukta) in Indian Mādhyamika School

sherry shi

https://www.academia.edu/42911366/Study_on_Four_Logical_Alternatives_catuṣkoṭi_and_catuṣkoṭi_vinirmukta_in_Indian_Mādhyamika_School

The Navya-Nyāya Doctrine of Negation. By Bimal K. Matilal.

Cambridge: Harvard University Press;

Canada: Saunders of Toronto, Ltd. 1968. Pp. xi, 208

Cyril Welch

Abhava : negation in logic, real non-existent, and a distinctive pramana in the Mimamsa

Purushottama Bilimoria PhD
2008, Logic Navya Nyaya and Applications Homage to Bimak Krishna Matilal

Thinking Negation in Early Hinduism and Classical Indian Philosophy

Purushottama Bilimoria PhD


https://doi.org/10.1007/s11787-017-0161-8
Publication Date: 2017
Publication Name: Logica Universalis

https://www.researchgate.net/publication/313941478_Thinking_Negation_in_Early_Hinduism_and_Classical_Indian_Philosophy

https://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/s11787-017-0161-8

Negation and the Law of Contradiction in Indian Thought: A Comparative Study

Published online by Cambridge University Press: 24 December 2009

J. F. Staal

https://www.cambridge.org/core/journals/bulletin-of-the-school-of-oriental-and-african-studies/article/abs/negation-and-the-law-of-contradiction-in-indian-thought-a-comparative-study/949A3A5C169D71859EF3440FA5A84D04

Part 19 – Negation in Nyāya-Vaiśeṣika

https://www.wisdomlib.org/hinduism/book/a-history-of-indian-philosophy-volume-1/d/doc209826.html

Basham, Kosambi, and the Negation of Negation

Ramkrishna Bhattacharya

https://www.academia.edu/11965736/Basham_Kosambi_and_the_Negation_of_Negation

Object Content and Relation

Publication Category Philosophers of Modern India
Publication Author Kalidas Bhattacharyya
Publication Language English
Publisher Name Das Gupta & Co.Ltd.
Publication Place Calcutta
No. of Pages 167

This book by Kalidas Bhattacharyya considers the relation between Consciousness and it’s Object. Once we ask the question “Is there anything intermediate between consciousness and object?”, we come up with the answer “Content”. Now, what is this Content and is there such an intermediate thing between Consciousness and Object? This is a question that needs to be answered. This book explores the relationship between Objects and Consciousness via the idea of Content. The book is divided into two chapters. This first chapter is on “Object and Content”. The second is on “Relation”. The first chapter deals with:

  • Analysis of Thought and Memory
  • Analysis of Perception: Idealism and Realism
  • Analysis of Perception – Illusion as to Judgment
  • Some Theories of Illusion Examined
  • Content and Object as Alternatives
  • Criterion of Reality
  • Real and Non-Real Appearances

The second chapter deals with

  • The Notion of Relation
  • Classification of Relations
  • The So-called Puzzles of Relation
  • Relation – Is it Subjective, Objective or Dialectical?
  • External and Internal Relation
  • Some Theories of Relation

Self, knowledge, and freedom: essays for Kalidas Bhattacharyya.

Bhattacharya, Kalidas ; Mohanty, Jitendranath & Banerjee, S. P. (eds.) (1978).

Kolkata: World Press.


THE VISVA-BHARATI JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY

Kalidas Bhattacharyya Memorial Number

Bulletin of The Department of Philosophy & Religion

EDITED BY PRADIP KUMAR SENGUPTA

Volume XXI : Number 1
August 1984

https://archive.org/details/in.ernet.dli.2015.95034

Books

Charles Sanders Peirce’s Continuum

Charles Sanders Peirce’s Continuum

Key Terms

  • Charles Sanders Peirce
  • Continumm
  • Continuity
  • Continua
  • Cantor’s Continua
  • Triadic Logic
  • Trivalent Logic
  • Three Valued Logic
  • Multi Valued Logic
  • Modality
  • Bivalent Logic
  • Cosmology
  • Infinite
  • Infinitesimal
  • Perception
  • Potentiality
  • Principle of Continuity
  • Realism
  • Synechism
  • Topology
  • Principle of Excluded Middle
  • Nested Continua Model

Continuity, Continuum, and Continua

  • What is Continuity, Continuum and Continua?
  • History of Continuum and Continua
  • Varieties of Continuum
  • Peirce’s Continuum
  • Continuum East and west
  • Peirce’s Nested Continua
  • Continuous and Discrete
  • Parts and No Parts (Whole)
  • Category Theory
  • Set Theory
  • Peirce’s Theory of Collections
  • Peirce’s Diagrams and Existential Graphs
  • Indivisibility
  • Number Theory and Mathematical Continuum
  • Topical/Topological Continuum
  • Cantor / Dedekind Continuum
  • Intuitive Continuum
  • Primordial Continuum
  • Large Set Theoretic Continuum
  • Category Theoretic Continuum
  • Sheaf Continuum
  • Euclidean Geometry
  • Non Euclidean Geometry
  • Archimedean Geometry
  • Non Archimedean Geometry
  • Complex Numbers and Fractals
  • Non Archimedean Systems
  • Nonstandard (Robinsonian) Continuum
  • Nilpotent Infinitesimalist Continuum
  • Point Free Continuum
  • Mereology
  • Mereotopology

History of Continua

Source: The History of Continua: Philosophical and Mathematical Perspectives

Mathematical and philosophical thought about continuity has changed considerably over the ages. Aristotle insisted that continuous substances are not composed of points, and that they can only be divided into parts potentially; a continuum is a unified whole. The most dominant account today, traced to Cantor and Dedekind, is in stark contrast with this, taking a continuum to be composed of infinitely many points. The opening chapters cover the ancient and medieval worlds: the pre-Socratics, Plato, Aristotle, Alexander, and a recently discovered manuscript by Bradwardine. In the early modern period, mathematicians developed the calculus the rise of infinitesimal techniques, thus transforming the notion of continuity. The main figures treated here include Galileo, Cavalieri, Leibniz, and Kant. In the early party of the nineteenth century, Bolzano was one of the first important mathematicians and philosophers to insist that continua are composed of points, and he made a heroic attempt to come to grips with the underlying issues concerning the infinite. The two figures most responsible for the contemporary hegemony concerning continuity are Cantor and Dedekind. Each is treated, along with precursors and influences in both mathematics and philosophy. The next chapters provide analyses of figures like du Bois-Reymond, Weyl, Brouwer, Peirce, and Whitehead. The final four chapters each focus on a more or less contemporary take on continuity that is outside the Dedekind–Cantor hegemony: a predicative approach, accounts that do not take continua to be composed of points, constructive approaches, and non-Archimedean accounts that make essential use of infinitesimals.

Keywords: continuity,  Aristotle,  infinity,  infinitesimal,  Dedekind,  Cantor,  pointintuitionism,  Archimedean,  indivisibles

Key Scholars

  • Plato
  • Aristotle
  • Parmenides
  • Zeno
  • Alexander of Aphrodisias
  • Thomas Bradwardine
  • Bernard Bolzano
  • Galileo Galilei
  • Bonaventura Cavalieri
  • Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz
  • Cauchey
  • Immanuel Kant
  • Georg Cantor
  • Richard Dedekind
  • Paul du Bois-Reymond
  • Hermann Weyl
  • Giuseppi Veronese
  • L. E. J. Brouwer
  • Alfred NorthWhitehead
  • Charles Sanders Peirce
  • Abraham Robinson

20th/21st Century Scholars

  • Matthew E. Moore
  • John L. Bell
  • Jerome Havenel
  • Fernando Zalamea
  • Gary Slater
  • Peter Ochs
  • Francesco Bellucci
  • Jon Alan Schmidt
  • D. A. Anapolitanos
  • D. Christopoulou
  • Robert Lane
  • Teppei Hayashi
  • Philip Ehrlich
  • Geoffrey Hellman
  • Stewart Shapiro
  • Marc Champagne

Varieties of Continua

Source: Varieties of Continua: From Regions to Points and Back

  • Ancient Atomism
  • Aristotle
  • Dedekind Cantor
  • Non Standard Analysis
  • Intuitionistic Analysis
  • Smooth Infinitesimal Analysis
  • Point based Predicative Analysis
  • Point Free Geometry and Analysis

Source: CONTEMPORARY INFINITESIMALIST THEORIES OF CONTINUA AND THEIR LATE 19TH- AND EARLY 20TH-CENTURY FORERUNNERS

  • Real Number System = Arithematic Continuum
  • Geometric Linear Continuum
  • Cantor Dedekind Axiom
  • Constructivist & Predicativist Theories
  • Infinitesimal Theories
    • Alain Connes’s Noncommutative (Differential) Geometry
    • Nonstandard Analysis
    • Nilpotent Infinitesimalist approaches to portions of differential geometry
    • Theory of Surreal Numbers
Emergence of Non Archimedean Systems of Magnitudes
  • Non archimedean geometry of G. Veronese
  • Tullio Levi-Civita
  • David Hilbert
  • Celebrated algebraico -set-theoretic work of Hans Hahn
  • du Bois-Reymond on the rates of growth of real functions
  • G. H. Hardy
  • Felix Hausdorff
Nonstandard Theories of Continua
  • Archimedean Axiom
  • Veronese’s Theory of Continua
  • Hahn’s non archimedean generalizations of the archimedean arithmetic continuum
  • Pantachies of du Bois-Reymond and Hausdorff
  • Elementary Continua
  • Nonstandard (Robinsonian) Continua
  • The absolute arithmetic continuum: Conway’s system of Surreal Numbers
  • Hjelmslev’s Nilpotent Infinitesimalist Continuum
  • Infinitesimalist Approches to differential geometry of Smooth Manifolds and their underlying continua
  • Invertible and Nilpotent infinitesimals afterthoughts

Charles Sanders Peirce’s Continuum

Evolution of Peirce’s Continuum

Source: Peirce on Continuity (Chapter 8 of Book by Vincent G Potter)

  • Pre Cantorian Until 1884
  • Cantorian 1884 – 1894
  • Kantistic 1895 – 1908
  • Post Cantorian 1908 – 1911

Source: Peirce’s Clarifications of Continuity / Jerome Havenel – Five Periods

  • Anti Nominalistic Period (1868 – 1884)
  • Cantorian Period (1884 – 1892)
  • Infinitesimal Period (1892 – 1897)
  • Super Multitudinous Period (1897 – 1907)
  • Topological Period (1908 – 1913)

Source: Logic of Relations and Diagrammatic Reasoning / Note 24

Scholars have explained how “continuity” is fundamental to Peirce’s mature philosophy; see Hookway (1985), Stjernfelt (2007) and Zalamea (2010). Moore (2015) evaluates Peirce’s description from a mathematical point of view. Dauben (1982) presents in some detail Peirce’s conception of the continuum from the point of view of set theory.

Source: The Continuity of Peirce’s Thought

A comprehensive and systematic reconstruction of the philosophy of Charles S. Peirce, perhaps America’s most far-ranging and original philosopher, which reveals the unity of his complex and influential body of thought. 

We are still in the early stages of understanding the thought of C. S. Peirce (1839-1914). Although much good work has been done in isolated areas, relatively little considers the Peircean system as a whole. Peirce made it his life’s work to construct a scientifically sophisticated and logically rigorous philosophical system, culminating in a realist epistemology and a metaphysical theory (“synechism”) that postulates the connectedness of all things in a universal evolutionary process. 

In The Continuity of Peirce’s Thought, Kelly Parker shows how the principle of continuity functions in phenomenology and semeiotics, the two most novel and important of Peirce’s philosophical sciences, which mediate between mathematics and metaphysics. Parker argues that Peirce’s concept of continuity is the central organizing theme of the entire Peircean philosophical corpus. He explains how Peirce’s unique conception of the mathematical continuum shapes the broad sweep of his thought, extending from mathematics to metaphysics and in religion. He thus provides a convenient and useful overview of Peirce’s philosophical system, situating it within the history of ideas and mapping interconnections among the diverse areas of Peirce’s work. 

This challenging yet helpful book adopts an innovative approach to achieve the ambitious goal of more fully understanding the interrelationship of all the elements in the entire corpus of Peirce’s writings. Given Peirce’s importance in fields ranging from philosophy to mathematics to literary and cultural studies, this new book should appeal to all who seek a fuller, unified understanding of the career and overarching contributions of Peirce, one of the key figures in the American philosophical tradition.

Source: Peirce’s Logic of continuity: a conceptual and mathematical approach to the continuum and the existential graphs

Peirce’s logic of continuity is explored from a double perspective: (i) Peirce’s original understanding of the continuum, alternative to Cantor’s analytical Real line, (ii) Peirce’s original construction of a topological logic – the existential graphs – alternative to the algebraic presentation of propositional and first-order calculi. Peirce’s general architectonics, oriented to back-and-forth hierarchical crossings between the global and the local, is reflected with great care both in the continuum and the existential graphs.

Source: Two New Gestures on Peirce’s Continuum and the Existential Graphs: Plurality of Pragmatic Imagination

Source: Two New Gestures on Peirce’s Continuum and the Existential Graphs: Plurality of Pragmatic Imagination

Source: Two New Gestures on Peirce’s Continuum and the Existential Graphs: Plurality of Pragmatic Imagination

Source: Two New Gestures on Peirce’s Continuum and the Existential Graphs: Plurality of Pragmatic Imagination

Source: Does Continuity Allow For Emergence?

The present paper proposes an emergentist reading of Peirce, with special reference to his concept of evolution. Although the author never adopts the word “emergence” in a technical manner, it will be demonstrated that the core problem of emergence lies at the heart of his evolutionary doctrine, generally displayed by the interplay of his three well-known categories of Firstness, Secondness and Thirdness. Indeed, although the Classical pragmatists most quoted in connection to emergentism are Dewey and Mead (and William James to some degree), scholars have recently suggested some emergentist readings of Peirce’s thought (cf. above all Tiercelin 1998, Quieroz & El-Hani 2006, Rose 2016), in particular with regard to semiotic process and cosmogony. Exploring further the path opened by those researches, the present paper aims to clarify the theoretical problem of emergent evolution from a pragmatist perspective and especially to illustrate Peirce’s emergentist standpoint. In order to reach this goal, the article is divided into four parts: after (1) a brief introduction to the contemporary debates on emergence, (2) I give a historical overview of Classical Pragmatism and British Emergentists, (3) with a special focus on the common roots of the British Emergentists and Peirce on evolution. Finally, (4) I offer an emergentist reading of Peirce’s theory of evolution. In particular, I show how his strong emphasis on chance and the “growth” of the universe go together with his arch-stone of synechism (that is his theory of continuity), through what he calls agapasm.

C. S. Peirce and the Nested Continua Model of Religious Interpretation

Source: C. S. Peirce and the Nested Continua Model of Religious Interpretation

The writings of the American pragmatist thinker Charles S. Peirce (1839–1914) provide resources for a hermeneutical model called the nested continua model of religious interpretation. A diagrammatic demonstration of iconic relational logic akin to Peirce’s Existential Graphs, the nested continua model is rendered as a series of concentric circles graphed upon a two-dimensional plane. When faced with some problem of interpretation, one may draw discrete markings that signify that problem’s logical distinctions, then represent in the form of circles successive contexts by which these distinctions may be examined in relation to one another, arranged ordinally at relative degrees of specificity and vagueness, aesthetic intensity, and concrete reasonableness. Drawing from Peter Ochs’s Scriptural Reasoning model of interfaith dialogue and Robert C. Neville’s axiology of thinking—each of which makes creative use of Peirce’s logic—this project aims to achieve an analytical unity between these two thinkers’ projects, which can then be addressed to further theological ends. The model hinges between diagrammatic and ameliorative functions, honing its logic to disclose contexts in which its theological or metaphysical claims might, if needed, be revised. These are claims made from a particular identity in a particular cultural context, but the logical rules upon which the claims are based are accessible to all. The book’s aims are to reconcile Neville’s and Ochs’s insights, explore the means by which phenomenal experience becomes encoded in texts and practices, and expand the capacity for comparing the texts and practices of one community with those of another.

Source: C. S. Peirce and the Nested Continua Model of Religious Interpretation / Review Notre Dame

Gary Slater has produced a highly original and intellectually sophisticated argument intended to develop resources in Charles S. Peirce’s philosophy for the purposes of contemporary philosophical theology. Toward that end, Slater articulates a “nested continua model” for religious interpretation early in the book, one indebted to Peirce’s “Existential Graphs,” a system of diagrams designed to provide a visual representation of the process of human reasoning. Although it has been the subject of considerable discussion, nevertheless, very few scholars have developed practical applications for Peirce’s system of graphs. Peter Ochs is an exception, having adapted Peirce’s logic for specifically theological purposes in an important book published in 1998. One of the valuable secondary contributions of Slater’s project is his successful attempt to place Ochs’ “postliberal” deliberations in productive conversation with Robert Neville’s straightforwardly liberal theology. (Along with Robert Corrington and Hermann Deuser, Ochs and Neville have been the most prominent and influential contemporary theological interpreters of Peirce’s philosophy.) As a result, Slater is able to formulate a perspective that combines a nuanced historicism with a robust metaphysics — a combination rare enough to be noteworthy.

The complexities of the nested continua model are unpacked at some length early in the book, initially in the Introduction and then with greater detail toward the end of the first chapter. This model involves the use of inscriptions drawn on a two-dimensional graph, both as specific markings and as a series of concentric circles. On Slater’s account, the model can be used in a variety of ways. Inspired by Neville’s metaphysical speculations, a point marked at the center of the graph would represent “absolute firstness,” the creative source of everything determinate in the universe. Emanating from this point, a series of nested circles can be imagined as portraying realities further and further removed from the act of creation, so that eternity would be represented by the space beyond the outermost circle. Each circle is a continuum, nested within continua of greater generality and “emerging” from those more determinate realities that it enframes. Using the model to illustrate the very different kind of analysis with which Ochs is preoccupied, each circle can also be regarded as supplying an interpretive framework for understanding everything that it contains, even as each framework is itself rendered meaningful by the broader contexts in which it is embedded. Slater observes that any two things that might be distinguished from each other can be marked on the graph as “A” and “B”; any circle drawn around them (“C”) signifies a rule of reasoning useful for interpreting these things. “The power of the model,” Slater suggests, “consists in its claim that any problem or interpretive framework can be graphed, and that the logical form for doing so — ‘A’ relates to ‘B’ with respect to some ‘C’ — remains consistent across all levels of generality” (p. 13).

In the second chapter Slater delineates the intellectual resources from which the nested continua model was developed, most of them Peircean in origin. Some of the difficulty in fully evaluating Slater’s project can be linked to certain unresolved problems in Peirce’s philosophy. Although Slater’s model is inspired by Peirce’s Existential Graphs, it should be noted that Peirce began to develop that iconic system of logic only late in his career; when he died this work remained sketchy, the Gamma graphs (devoted to modal logic) having never been completed. Peirce’s logical deliberations, moreover, were informed by his study of the topology of Johann Listing, a 19th century mathematician whose approach to the subject differs dramatically from that of later 20th and 21st century topologists. Similarly, Peirce’s concept of the infinitesimal, appropriated by Slater for multiple purposes (including his account of how continua emerge one from another), was never fully developed, leaning on the earlier work of his father Benjamin and only vaguely anticipating the way in which this concept would later be employed by Abraham Robinson in his formulation of non-standard analysis (in the 1960’s). Surely Peirce’s investigations in logic, topology and the mathematics of the infinitesimal must be regarded as unfinished business.

It should be noted that Peirce regarded any two-dimensional graph as being inadequate for the purposes of his modal logic. For the Gamma system, not a single “sheet of assertion,” but rather a three-dimensional “book of sheets, tacked together at points” would be required. This conclusion is consistent with Peirce’s critique of Josiah Royce’s map metaphor, articulated in his review of the latter’s Gifford Lectures on The World and the Individual; that map would have to be conceived as only a “section” of some three-dimensional projection. Slater himself recognizes this limitation of his model, admitting that “change itself cannot be rendered on the graph, which is after all a two-dimensional space” (p. 103). His choice is to work within this limitation rather than attempt to develop the model, thus understanding change “in terms of infinitesimal emergence.” He further admits that this move involves leaning on a concept of “emergence” that “Peirce himself did not use” (p. 85).

Whatever the limitations of Slater’s nested continua model, the ingenuity displayed in his articulation of it is impressive. Moreover, he is careful to modestly circumscribe claims about its potential usefulness, insisting that its employment ought to be understood as only a starting point for any theological inquiry (p. 209). Early on, he describes it as “a kind of abductive Petri dish” for the purpose of testing various theological hypotheses (p. 75). It facilitates a process of experimental thinking and the clarification of vague ideas, especially in the early stages of inquiry. Rather than constituting a full-blown theological method, then, Slater envisions the graphing as playing a key but limited role in such a method.

On my evaluation, the general utility of the model (as with Peirce’s existential graphs) consists in its pronounced ability to direct attention for the purpose of making certain inferences (what Slater typically refers to as “willful awareness”), thus displaying the crucial role that attention plays in all forms of human reasoning. (Consider Slater’s insightful discussion of “Prescisive and Habit-Conditioned Reasoning” on pages 79-82 — although I think that Slater conflates “prescision” with “hypostatic abstraction” in a way that he might be more careful to avoid.) The iconic features of the model also enable Slater to avoid the pitfalls of what he refers to as “linguistic determinism” (p. 122); unlike certain contemporary neo-pragmatists, Slater is disinclined to reduce semiosis to language, or limit interpretation to verbal behavior.

With regard to particular uses of the model here, there are also some moments of extraordinary insight, highly original ideas that would be well worth developing. One consists in Slater’s use of the nested continua model as an analytical tool to safeguard against metaphysical absolutism or idolatry, playing on the contrast in the model between “translucent” and “opaque” circles of interpretation. Another, toward the end of the book, involves his establishing a link between love and “singular evil” via the Scotistic concept of haecceity (pp. 193-98); since both presuppose an awareness of the radically individual character of things it makes sense on his account to describe such evil as a kind of “love gone wrong.” This is nicely done. There are also tantalizing suggestions about a type of “Thirdness” that might be shown to function “as the ultimate logical interpretant with regard to prayer” (p. 157; although the promise to develop this suggestion in a later chapter is only partially redeemed).

However one might evaluate the virtues or shortcomings of Slater’s logical model, on my reading, the significance of this book can by no means be reduced to such an evaluation. For example, the discussion and critique of theological supersessionism is thoughtful and illuminating, even while it is not linked closely enough to the nested continua model to demonstrate how or even that the model is required for the purposes of this discussion. Slater’s recognition that theological reflection takes multiple forms and so cannot be reduced to a set of responses to problematic beliefs or situations mirrors his nuanced interpretation of Peirce’s philosophy. While careful to note that Peirce’s full-blown theory of inquiry is capacious enough to embrace both the early “stimulus of doubt” account and the later portrayal of musement, Slater wisely avoids driving any kind of deep wedge between Peirce’s initial pragmatism and his eventual “pragmaticism.” The summary of key intellectual influences on Peirce’s philosophy in the book’s first chapter is a model of clarity. And since Peirce wrote very little about the topic, Slater’s creative gesturing “Toward a Peircean Philosophy of History” in chapter three deserves careful consideration

As already indicated, Slater’s attempt to mediate between the contrasting philosophical and theological perspectives articulated by Ochs and Neville represents a significant achievement. His sensitive reading of these two important but sometimes neglected interpreters of Peirce is scattered throughout the book, but forms the bulk of chapters four and five. Ochs’ portrayal of “scriptural reasoning” as an historically conditioned mode of “repair” and Neville’s account of all human thought as being intrinsically and essentially “axiological” represent a challenging subject matter rendered lucid by Slater’s treatment.

Yet Slater’s attention is by no means limited to the work of these two figures. He provides perhaps the most comprehensive overview to date of the scholarly conversation devoted to Peirce’s relevance for theology and religious studies. This overview extends back to the pioneering labors of John E. Smith, includes discussion of Corrington’s “ecstatic naturalism” as well as my own investigations in “theosemiotic,” and then proceeds to incorporate insights gleaned from the work of a small group of younger scholars (such as Leon Niemoczynski, Anette Ejsing, Abraham Robinson and Brandon Daniel-Hughes) who are presently shaping that conversation in new and interesting ways. With the publication of this book, Gary Slater now occupies a prominent place in this latter group. His voice is an original one, his scholarly range impressive (so that his reading of pragmatism registers points of view as disparate as those of Robert Brandom and Sandra Rosenthal). The bold creativity of his model is likely to attract the attention of numerous readers. The insightful application of that model to important issues in the study of religion should both sustain and reward such attention.

Source: A Visual Model of Peirce’s 66 Classes of Signs Unravels His Late Proposal of Enlarging Semiotic Theory

Source: A Less Simplistic Metaphysics: Peirce’s Layered Theory of Meaning as a Layered Theory of Being

Source: PEIRCE’S CONTINUUM: A METHODOLOGICAL AND MATHEMATICAL APPROACH

Source: PEIRCE’S CONTINUUM: A METHODOLOGICAL AND MATHEMATICAL APPROACH

Source: PEIRCE’S CONTINUUM: A METHODOLOGICAL AND MATHEMATICAL APPROACH

Continuum East and West

THE CONTINUUM EAST AND WEST Peter G. Jones
Philosophy Pathways, 185, May 2014

This essay examines the relationship between mysticism, for which Buddhism’s Middle Way doctrine would serve here as a defining example, and what, for want of better word, we call ‘Western’ philosophy. This is an issue of general interest to philosophers, since sooner or later in our investigations we must all decide whether the ‘Western’ kind of philosophy makes more or less sense to us than the ‘Eastern’ kind.

One obstacle we face in trying to make this decision is the difficulty of discerning clearly the defining characteristics of the two philosophies, those features that lead us to make such a final and definite distinction between them in the first place. We commonly speak of ‘Eastern’ and ‘Western’ philosophy, but are not so commonly able to say quite what we mean by this. The relevant issues are profound, mind-bending and probably inexhaustible. They need not be complicated, and they are often quite simple, but they are always immensely challenging.

One of these simple (stripped of the details) yet challenging issues would be the true nature of the continuum. The discussion that follows outlines the view of physicist, mathematician and philosopher Hermann Weyl. Weyl makes a careful distinction between the ‘arithmetical’ continuum, the continuum conceived of as an extended object, as it must be for the real numbers and space-time, and the ‘intuitive’ continuum, the empirical continuum of experience, which is not extended, and he demonstrates that when we set out to define what we mean by ‘Eastern’ and ‘Western’ philosophy, the foundations of analysis would be a good place to start. The interconnectedness of all the relevant issues at a foundational level, for all roads lead to Rome, means that we may as well start where we like, but mathematics takes us immediately to what might be the most clearly discernable and easily described difference between the two philosophies and worldviews, perhaps also the most general and profound, namely their entirely different conceptions of the continuum.

As there is just one source for each author quoted here I have not added numbered references but just tried to make it clear who is talking. Italics are always original.

>><<

In The Continuum: A Critical Examination of the Foundations of Analysis, Hermann Weyl points out that the extended space-time of physics and ordinary perception is, in the same way as the number line, a construction of reason and not intuitively or empirically given. He addresses a problem that arises in different guises but with an equal vengeance in religion, physics, mathematics and metaphysics. It is the problem of modelling a continuum as an extended series of discrete locations or ‘things’, as we do must do for the number line, geometry and arithmetic, space and time, and even for our very concept of the continuum, when a series of discrete locations or ‘things’ is exactly and precisely what a continuum is not.

A continuum cannot be extended as a series of points or moments for the reasons Weyl gives below, and yet it must be in order for anything to be extended in space and time. This causes a problem in philosophy. It would be a ‘first-order’ metaphysical problem or ‘antinomy’, a straight choice between two ideas neither of which work. It would be closely connected with the question of how many angels can dance on the head of a pin, of how small we can make an angel before it becomes the ‘ghost of a departed quantity’. The various problems and paradoxes to which the intellectually-constructed continuum of the arithmetical line gives rise has no impact on the usefulness of mathematics, which is wholly dependent on this conception, but it indicates that the continuum of space-time is not an equivalent case and is, rather, a true continuum. As such, it would not be a set of locations but a unity. A unity has no parts. This would suggest that space and time are conceptual imputations and that Reality, whatever is truly and independently-real amongst all the smoke and mirrors, is not in fact extended. This is a difficult idea but not a new one, and it is widely popular in religion. When theoretical physicists say ‘distance is arbitrary’, perhaps they are suggesting something similar. It might at least help to explain how a Big Bang can appear to have occurred before there is, was or ever will be a time or a place for it to have happened. For an ultimate view it would not have happened. If the continuum cannot have parts then all co-ordinate systems are emergent.

Here is Tobias Dantzig, a mathematician admired by Einstein, introducing the issues.

Herein I see the genesis of the conflict between geometrical intuition, from which our physical concepts derive, and the logic of arithmetic. The harmony of the universe knows only one musical form – the legato; while the symphony of numbers knows only its opposite, – the staccato. All attempts to reconcile this discrepancy are based on the hope that an accelerated staccato may appear to our senses as legato. Yet our intellect will always brand such attempts as deceptions and reject such theories as an insult, as a metaphysics that purports to explain away a concept by resolving it into its opposite.

While a series of points serves perfectly well for the continuum of the number line and arithmetic, on examination it is a paradoxical idea that must be rejected in both metaphysics and physics as a model of space-time. The continuum of physics is, at this time, extended as a series of points and moments, and as such no sense can be made of it. Viewed as a real phenomenon a continuum so-defined would either be paradoxical or fail to qualify for the name. We have every right to define the continuum for mathematics as we currently do, and if our idea is paradoxical then it is only a problem when we investigate the foundations of analysis. When we define the continuum for mathematics we are not making a claim about the nature of Reality. Elsewhere it would be a different matter. In metaphysics we certainly cannot adopt a priori an arithmetical definition of the continuum. Insofar as it relates to metaphysics this might be the central message of Weyl’s book. At the same time, physics and ordinary perception are heavily theory-laden, dangerously so. Our usual everyday theory is that time and space are extended in just the same way as is the number line, such that space- and time-points can be represented as locations in an extended co-ordinate system. But is there any evidence that space and time are extended objects? What is it that our wristwatch is actually measuring? Are we quite sure that our usual theory of extension, for which space-time would be a ‘classical’ or Newtonian phenomenon, is fundamentally correct? Is it a metaphysical conjecture, a testable scientific theory, something we know from experience or a highly evolved misinterpretation? For our Western tradition of philosophy this would be a famously undecidable problem. Here the continuum appears to be paradoxical, for it cannot be extended ex hypothesis, and yet, by some magic, it is. Or it seems to be. For the Eastern tradition this everyday theory of space-time would be testable and it would fail the tests, being refutable in logic and falsifiable in experience. The continuum would be a unity, just as its name implies.

Weyl reduces the conceptually extended continuum of mathematics and traditional physics to what he calls the ‘true’ or ‘intuitive’ continuum, where the latter is carefully distinguished from the former. The intuitive continuum, the continuum as we experience it, is not extended as a series of moments or points. We do not experience time and space as consisting of moments and points, or, if we do, it is only ever the same moment and point. We are always here and now. What is more, there is actually something very odd about the idea that space and time are ‘grainy’ in this way. The length of ten thousand points would be equal to the length of one point, for a start, so no amount of points would be sufficient to construct basic geometry, let alone a piano. In the same way, no amount of moments would be sufficient to account for motion and change. Space and time are explanatory theories, Weyl proposes, generated by reason and imagination, not empirical phenomena.

For an orthodox view of space-time here is a passage from Wikipedia from the entry for Hermann Minkowsky.

This new reality was that space and time, as physical constructs, have to be combined into a new mathematical/physical entity called ‘space-time’, because the equations of relativity show that both the space and time coordinates of any event must get mixed together by the mathematics, in order to accurately describe what we see. Because space consists of 3 dimensions, and time is 1- dimensional, space-time must, therefore, be a 4-dimensional object. It is believed to be a ‘continuum’ because so far as we know, there are no missing points in space or instants in time, and both can be subdivided without any apparent limit in size or duration. So, physicists now routinely consider our world to be embedded in this 4-dimensional Space-Time continuum, and all events, places, moments in history, actions and so on are described in terms of their location in Space-Time.

Dantzig explores the origins of this co-ordinate system.

The notion of equal-greater-less precedes the number concept. We learn to compare before we lean to evaluate. Arithmetic does not begin with numbers; it begins with criteria. Having learnt to apply these criteria of equal-greater-less, man’s next step was to devise models for each type of plurality. These models are deposited in his memory very much as the standard meter is deposited at the Bureau of Longitudes in Paris. One, two, three, four, five …; we could just as well have said: I,

wings, clover, legs, hand … and, for all we know, the latter preceded our present form.

He goes on to observe that the staccato of the numbers is not empirical or intuitive, but a superimposition.

It is possible to assign to any point on a line a unique real number, and, conversely, any real number can be represented in a unique manner by a point on the line.

This is the famous Dedekind-Cantor axiom. This proposition, by sanctifying the tacit assumption on which analytical geometry had operated for over two hundred years, became the fundamental axiom of this discipline. It defines a new mathematical being, the arithmetical line. Henceforth the line – and consequently the plane, and space – ceases to be an intuitive notion and is reduced to being a mere carrier of numbers.

In the following passage Dantzig notes the paradoxical nature of the arithmetical line. This matters little in mathematics, but when the arithmetical line is taken to be a model of the true continuum it renders Reality paradoxical and causes philosophical havoc, in particular a deep rift between two quite different traditions of philosophy.

The axiom of Dedekind – “if all points of a straight line fall into two classes, such that every point of the first class lies to the left of any point of the second class, then there exists one and only one point which produces this division of all points into two classes, this severing of the straight line into two portions” – this axiom is just a skilful paraphrase of the fundamental property we attribute to time. Our intuition permits us, by an act of the mind, to sever all time into the two classes, the past and the future, which are mutually exclusive and yet together comprise all of time, eternity: The now is the partition which separates all the past from all the future; any instant of the past was once a now, any instant of the future will be a now anon, and so any instant may itself act as such a partition. To be sure, of the past we know only disparate instants, yet, by an act of the mind we fill out the gaps; we conceive that between any two instants – no matter how closely these may be associated in our memory – there were other instants, and we postulate the same compactness for the future. This is what we mean by the flow of time.

Furthermore, paradoxical though this may seem, the present is truly irrational in the Dedekind sense of the word, for while it acts as partition it is neither a part of the past nor a part of the future. Indeed, in an arithmetic based on pure time, if such an arithmetic was at all possible, it is the irrational which would be taken as a matter of course, while all the painstaking efforts of our logic would be directed toward establishing the existence of rational numbers.

In other words, the Dedekind sense of the word ‘present’ is irrational. Space-time cannot have the properties he assigns to the number line unless the Cosmos is irrational. This is the problem addressed by Weyl. He deals with it by making a clear distinction between the intuitive or experienced continuum, the intuition of the continuum that for all of us is an empirical phenomenon, and the intellectually constructed faux-continuum of Dedekind’s arithmetical line. They could hardly be more different.

To the criticism that the intuition of the continuum in no way contains those logical principles on which we must rely for the exact definition of the concept “real number,” we respond that the conceptual world of mathematics is so foreign to what the intuitive continuum presents to us that the demand for coincidence between the two must be dismissed as absurd.

He points out that the usefulness of the arithmetical line has no bearing on its plausibility as a model of the space-time continuum.

Whichever view of the relation of mathematics to nature one takes, there is no independent physical conception of the continuum on offer in all this, since all the mathematics is filtered through the real number system (or Hilbertian geometry as a surrogate). Moreover, I don’t see that any argument can be made from the enormously successful applications of mathematics in natural science to the conclusion that one or another of the mathematical conceptions of the continuum surveyed above is uniquely singled out as the “real one”. In any case, the work on the reach of predicative mathematics cited at the end of the preceding section shows that the properties of the continuum needed for its applications in natural science do not require it to have a definite reality in the platonistic sense.

Here is extract from an essay on Weyl and the continuum by John Bell.

…Weyl regards the experienced continuous flow of phenomenal time as constituting an insuperable barrier to the whole enterprise of representing this continuum in terms of individual points, and even to the characterization of “individual temporal point” itself. As he says,

“The view of a flow consisting of points and, therefore, also dissolving into points turns out to be mistaken: precisely what eludes us is the nature of the continuity, the flowing from point to point; in other words, the secret of how the continually enduring present can continually slip away into the receding past.

Each one of us, at every moment, directly experiences the true character of this temporal continuity. But, because of the genuine primitiveness of phenomenal time, we cannot put our experiences into words. So we shall content ourselves with the following description. What I am conscious of is for me both a being-now and,

in its essence, something which, with its temporal position, slips away. In this way there arises the persisting factual extent, something ever new which endures and changes in consciousness.”

We see here that an examination of the foundations of analysis leads us immediately into the realms of psychology, physics, metaphysics, religion, consciousness studies and more. Bell continues.

Weyl sums up what he thinks can be affirmed about “objectively presented time”— by which I take it he means “phenomenal time described in an objective manner”— in the following two assertions, which he claims apply equally, mutatis mutandis, to every intuitively given continuum, in particular, to the continuum of spatial extension:

1. An individual point in it is non-independent, i.e., is pure nothingness when taken by itself, and exists only as a “point of transition” (which, of course, can in no way be understood mathematically);

2. It is due to the essence of time (and not to contingent imperfections in our medium) that a fixed temporal point cannot be exhibited in any way, that always only an approximate, never an exact determination is possible.

The fact that single points in a true continuum “cannot be exhibited” arises, Weyl continues, from the fact that they are not genuine individuals and so cannot be characterized by their properties. In the physical world they are never defined absolutely, but only in terms of a coordinate system, which, in an arresting metaphor, Weyl describes as “the unavoidable residue of the eradication of the ego.”

In particular, he found compelling the fact that the Brouwerian continuum is not the union of two disjoint nonempty parts— that it is, in a word, indecomposable. “A genuine continuum,” Weyl says, “cannot be divided into separate fragments.” In later publications he expresses this more colourfully by quoting Anaxagoras to the effect that a continuum “defies the chopping off of its parts with a hatchet.”

Weyl’s book on the continuum delves little further into metaphysical issues than is necessary for his examination of analysis. Elsewhere he says more, and we find a clear connection between his mathematico-philosophical views and Buddhism’s theory of emptiness and doctrine of dependent origination. As far as it goes his book on the continuum could be read as a mathematical explanation of the universe of the perennial philosophy, and of how it differs from that of the Western tradition in at least one vital respect. Bell makes the correlation clear.

In The Open World (1932), Weyl provides an eloquent formulation of his philosophical outlook, which quickly moves beyond its initial echoes of Schopenhauer:

“The beginning of all philosophical thought is the realization that the perceptual world is but an image, a vision, a phenomenon of our consciousness; our consciousness does not directly grasp a transcendental real world which is as it appears. The tension between subject and object is no doubt reflected in our conscious acts, for example, in sense perceptions. Nevertheless, from the purely epistemological point of view, no objection can be made to a phenomenalism which would like to limit science to the description of what is “immediately given to consciousness”. The postulation of the real ego, of the thou and of the world, is a metaphysical matter, not judgment, but an act of acknowledgment and belief.

But this belief is after all the soul of all knowledge. It was an error of idealism to assume that the phenomena of consciousness guarantee the reality of the ego in an essentially different and somehow more certain way than the reality of the external world; in the transition from consciousness to reality the ego, the thou and the world rise into existence indissolubly connected and, as it were, at one stroke.”

Any comparison of ‘Eastern’ and ‘Western’ approaches to philosophy must eventually end up here, examining the question of whether the continuum of space-time is arithmetical and paradoxical, or whether it would make more sense to say that spatio-temporal extension is an interpretation of appearances, a relationship between appearances, and not an empirical or even truly real phenomenon. Whichever way we decide this question, an examination of these issues will reveal a clear and crucial difference of opinion between East and West over the ultimate nature of Reality.

It is absurdly misleading to use the words ‘Western’ and ‘Eastern’ to describe two philosophical camps, and really it is dualism and nondualism that we are comparing here, both of which appear all over the world. Whatever words we use, mathematics can help us to pin down our definitions in important respects.

Weyl summarises his view as follows.

The category of the natural numbers can supply the foundation of a mathematical discipline. But perhaps the continuum cannot, since it fails to satisfy the requirements [mentioned in Chapter1]: as basic a notion as that of the point in the continuum lacks the required support in intuition. It is to the credit of Bergson’s philosophy to have pointed out forcefully this deep division between the world of mathematical concepts

and the immediately experienced continuity of phenomenal time.

The view of a flow consisting of points and, therefore, also dissolving into points turns out to be false. Precisely what eludes us is the nature of the continuity, the flowing from point to point; in other words, the secret of how the continually enduring present can continually slip away into the receding past….

…When our experience has turned into a real process in a real world and our phenomenal time has spread itself out over this world and assumed a cosmic dimension, we are not satisfied with replacing the continuum by the exact concept of the real numbers, in spite of the essential and undeniable inexactness arising from what is given. For, as always, there is more at work here than heavy-handed schematizing or cognitive economizing devised for fulfilling our practical tasks and objectives. Here we discover genuine reason which lays bare the “Logos” dwelling in reality (just as purely as is possible for this consciousness which cannot “leap over its own shadow”). But to discuss this further cannot be our business here. Certainly, the intuitive and the mathematical continuum do not coincide; a deep chasm is fixed between them….

…The reflections contained in this section are, of course, only a slightly illuminating surrogate for a genuine philosophy of the continuum. But since no penetrating treatment of this topic is at hand and since our task is mathematical rather than epistemological, the matter can rest there.

For a book on analysis it would have been inappropriate for Weyl to say more about this. If we are examining the pivotal questions on which Eastern and Western philosophies are divided, however, then the matter cannot rest here. The former philosophy makes a claim about the continuum that is denied point-blank by the latter. It may still be true that ‘no penetrating treatment of this topic is at hand’, at least outside of the ‘mystical’ literature, but this would not reflect on the importance of this topic across all of philosophy, and it need not prevent us from forming a view on which of these two philosophical approaches gives the most plausible description of space and time.

Is space-time extended or is it a continuum? Weyl suggest that we cannot have it both ways. Nagarjuna’s Middle Way Buddhism, which is infuriatingly stubborn when it comes to endorsing extreme views on any topic, would say that the question is not quite answerable in this straightforward form. There would be a sense in which it is neither and a sense in which it is both. There is not a straightforward disagreement between East and West on the answer to this question, therefore, with the two sides adopting equal and opposite views. All the same, it seems true to say that the very different answers they give to this question reveal one of the most crucial and far-reaching differences between these two traditions of philosophical thought.

Bibliography

Bell, John L, ‘Hermann Weyl on intuition and the continuum’.

Click to access Hermann%20Weyl.pdf

Dantzig, Tobias, Number – The Language of Science, (Pearson Education 2005 (1930)

Weyl, Hermann, The Continuum: A Critical Examination of the Foundations of Analysis, Dover (1987)

My Related Posts

Charles Sanders Peirce’s Visual Logic: Diagrams and Existential Graphs

Charles Sanders Peirce’s Theory of Signs

The Aesthetics of Charles Sanders Peirce

Indra’s Net: On Interconnectedness

The Great Chain of Being

Maha Vakyas: Great Aphorisms in Vedanta

On Synchronicity

Key Sources of Research

Implications of Synechism: Continuity and Second-Order Vagueness

Implicações do Sinequismo: Lógica Triádica e Vagueza de Segunda Ordem

Marco Annoni

Università di Pisa – Italia

marcoabrema@hotmail.com

COGNI TI O-ESTUDOS: Revista Eletrônica de Filosofia

Centro de Estudos do Pragmatismo – Programa de Estudos Pós-Graduados em Filosofia – Pontifícia Universidade Católica de São Paulo

São Paulo, Volume 3, Número 2, p. 096- 108, TEXTO 11/3.2, julho/dezembro, 2006

https://www.academia.edu/1965259/Implications_of_Synechism_Continuity_and_Second_Order_Vagueness

Continuity as vagueness: The mathematical antecedents of Peirce’s semiotics*

PETER OCHS

Semiotica 96-3/4 (1993), 231-255 0037-1998/93/0096-0231

https://www.academia.edu/19870302/Continuity_as_vagueness_The_mathematical_antecedents_of_Peirces_semiotics

Peirce and Brouwer

Conor Mayo-Wilson

September 5, 2011

https://www.academia.edu/954648/Peirce_and_Brouwer

Peirce, Leibniz, and the threshold of pragmatism

Francesco Bellucci

Semiotica 2013; 195: 331 – 355
DOI 10.1515/sem-2013-0030

Dynamical Interpretation of Leibniz’s Continuum

Vassil VIDINSKY*

Peirce and Leibniz on Continuity and the
Continuum

D. A. Anapolitanos and D. Christopoulou*

*Corresponding author: D. Christopoulou, Assistant Professor Mathematics Department, Kapodistrian University of Athens, Athens, Greece, E-mail: chrdemet@yahoo.gr
D. A. Anapolitanos, History and Philosophy of Science Department, National and Kapodistrian University of Athens, Athens, Greece, E-mail: danap@phs.uoa.gr

Metaphysica 2020; aop

https://doi.org/10.1515/mp-2019-0008

https://www.academia.edu/44132364/Peirce_and_Leibniz_on_Continuity_and_the_Continuum_with_D_Anapolitanos_

Peirce’s Topological Concepts

Jérôme Havenel

Draft version of the book chapter published in
New Essays on Peirce’s Philosophy of Mathematics,
Matthew E. Moore ed, Open Court, 2010

Peirce’s Logic of Continuity

A Conceptual and Mathematical Approach

Fernando Zalamea

Book

https://www.academia.edu/31948393/ZalameaPeirceCont_pdf

Peirce’s Clarifications of Continuity

Jérôme Havenel

Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society: A Quarterly Journal
in American Philosophy, Volume 44, Number 1, Winter 2008,
pp. 86-133 (Article)

Published by Indiana University Press
DOI: 10.1353/csp.0.0001

https://www.researchgate.net/publication/236774797_Peirce%27s_Clarifications_of_Continuity

«Peirce’s meditations on continuity: from transitivity to topology»,

Havenel, J. (2015).

en: Zalemea, Fernando y Oostra, Arnold (eds).

Cuadernos de Sistemática Peirceana. Vol. 7,. Bogotá: Editorial Nomos, pp. 101-126.

Peirce’s Continuous Predicates

FRANCESCO BELLUCCI

Transactions of the Charles S Peirce Society

A Quarterly Journal in American Philosophy · April 2013
DOI: 10.2979/trancharpeirsoc.49.2.178

https://www.researchgate.net/publication/259734578_Peirce%27s_Continuous_Predicates

“Peirce’s Definitions of Continuity”

Potter, V. G.; Shields, S. J. (1977):

Transactions of the Charles Sanders Peirce Society, v. 13, n. 1, pp. 20-34.

Synechism: the Keystone of Peirce’s Metaphysics

Joseph Esposito

http://www.commens.org/encyclopedia/article/esposito-joseph-synechism-keystone-peirce’s-metaphysics

Peirce’s Logic of continuity: a conceptual and mathematical approach to the continuum and the existential graphs.

Zalamea, F. (2012).

Boston: Docent Press.

«Leibniz on Continuity»,

Arthur, R. (1986).

en: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science, Science Association, Vol. 1986, Volume One: Contributed Papers, pp. 107-115

«Continuity in Leibniz’s Mature Metaphysics»,

Crockett, T. (May, 1999).

en: Philosophical Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition, Vol. 94, No. 1/2, Selected Papers Presented at the American Philosophical Association Pacific Division Meeting 1998, pp. 119-138.

«Peirce and Leibniz»,

Fisch, M. (Jul.-Sep. 1972).

en: Journal of the History of Ideas. Vol. 33, No. 3, Festschrift for Philip P. Wiener, pp. 485-496

The idea of continuity in the philosphies of Leibniz and Peirce.

Flórez Restrepo, J. A., & Arias Cardona, J. E. (2022).

Pensamiento. Revista De Investigación E Información Filosófica, 78(298 S. Esp), 841-861. https://doi.org/10.14422/pen.v78.i298.y2022.030

https://revistas.comillas.edu/index.php/pensamiento/article/view/10977

“On Peirce’s Discovery of Cantor’s Theorem.”

Moore, Matthew E. 2007.

Cognitio 8: 223–48.

“Peirce’s Cantor.”

Moore, Matthew E. 2011.

in New Essays on Peirce’s Mathematical Philosophy, ed. Matthew E. Moore. Chicago: Open Court.

“Peirce on Cantor’s Paradox and the Continuum.” 

Myrvold, Wayne C. 1995.

Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 31 (3): 508–41.

PATTERNHOOD, CORRELATION, AND GENERALITY: FOUNDATIONS OF A PEIRCEAN THEORY OF PATTERNS

Jimmy Jericho Aames

Master of Arts Thesis
in the Department of Philosophy
Indiana University
July 2016

https://scholarworks.iupui.edu/bitstream/handle/1805/10896/Thesis%2007052016.pdf?sequence=1

Peirce-Related Papers

Bibliography

Indiana University

https://arisbe.sitehost.iu.edu/menu/library/aboutcsp/ABOUTCSP.HTM

Charles Sanders Peirce

Wikipedia

https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Charles_Sanders_Peirce

Peirce’s “Extreme” Realism and Supermultitudinous Conception of Continuity

Jimmy Aames

Indiana University-Purdue University Indianapolis

Department of Philosophy MAE-mail:  jjaames@iupui.edu

2015

https://www.academia.edu/12635422/Peirces_Extreme_Realism_and_Supermultitudinous_Conception_of_Continuity

Peirce on Continuity: Vindication of Universals against Nominalism

Paniel Reyes Cardenas

2014, Hannah, Patricia (Ed),An Anthology of Philosophical Studies 8

https://www.academia.edu/7005464/Peirce_on_Continuity_Vindication_of_Universals_against_Nominalism

Mathematical Structuralism, Continuity and Peirce’s Diagrammatic Reasoning

Paniel Reyes Cardenas

https://www.academia.edu/1540932/Mathematical_Structuralism_Continuity_and_Peirces_Diagrammatic_Reasoning

Bateson and Peirce on the Pattern that Connects and the Sacred

Søren Brier

2008, A Legacy for Living Systems

https://www.academia.edu/725104/Bateson_and_Peirce_on_the_Pattern_that_Connects_and_the_Sacred

Philosophy of Mathematics
Selected Writings
Charles S. Peirce

Edited by
Matthew E. Moore

INDIANA UNIVERSITY PRESS 2010

Bloomington and Indianapolis

Peirce and the Continuum from a Philosophical Point of View.

Zink, J. (2001).

In: Schuster, P., Berger, U., Osswald, H. (eds) Reuniting the Antipodes — Constructive and Nonstandard Views of the Continuum. Synthese Library, vol 306. Springer, Dordrecht.

https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-9757-9_25

https://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1007/978-94-015-9757-9_25

Peirce’s Topical Continuum: A “Thicker” Theory

Jon Alan Schmidt

TRANSACTIONS OF THE CHARLES S. PEIRCE SOCIETY Vol. 56, No. 1 (2020) • doi: 10.2979/trancharpeirsoc.56.1.04

https://philarchive.org/archive/SCHPTC-2

Charles Sanders Peirce and the Principle of Bivalence

Robert Lane

1998

https://www.academia.edu/660658/Charles_Sanders_Peirce_and_the_Principle_of_Bivalence


The genesis of the Peircean continuum

Matthew E. Moore
Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 43 (3):425 – 469 (2007)

Peirce’s topical theory of continuity.

Moore, Matthew E. (2015).

Synthese 192 (4):1-17.

Peirce’s Triadic Logic Revisited

Lane, Robert (1999).

Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 35 (2):284 – 311.

Peirce’s Graphs—The Continuity Interpretation.

Zeman, J. Jay (1968).

Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 4 (3):144 – 154.

Peirce on Continuity and Laws of Nature.

Sfendoni-Mentzou, Demetra (1997).

Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 33 (3):646 – 678.

Questions concerning Peirce’s Agapic Continuity.

Staab, Janice M. (1999).

Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 35 (1):157 – 176.

Peirce’s Definitions of Continuity and the Concept of Possibility.

Noble, N. A. Brian (1989).

Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 25 (2):149 – 174.

Peirce’s Potential Continuity and Pure Geometry.

Hudry, Jean-Louis (2004).

Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 40 (2):229 – 243.

The Continuity of Peirce’s Thought.

Colapietro, Vincent (1999).

The Personalist Forum 15 (2):432-437.

Continuity and Inheritance: Kant’s “Critique of Judgment” and the Work of C. S. Peirce.

Kaag, John (2005).

Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 41 (3):515 – 540.

Peirce’s evolutionary logic: Continuity, indeterminacy, and the natural order.

Alborn, Timothy L. (1989).

Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 25 (1):1 – 28.

Peirce’s mathematical-logical approach to discrete collections and the premonition of continuity.

Rebello Cardoso, Helio (2012).

Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 22 (1-2):11-28.

The Peircean Continuum

Vargas, Francisco, and Matthew E. Moore, 

in Stewart Shapiro, and Geoffrey Hellman (eds), The History of Continua: Philosophical and Mathematical Perspectives (Oxford, 2020; online edn, Oxford Academic, 17 Dec. 2020), https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198809647.003.0014, accessed 31 Mar. 2023.

The History of Continua: Philosophical and Mathematical Perspectives 

Shapiro, Stewart, and Geoffrey Hellman (eds), 

(Oxford, 2020; online edn, Oxford Academic, 17 Dec. 2020), https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198809647.001.0001, accessed 31 Mar. 2023.

Peirce’s Topological Concepts

Jérôme Havenel

Draft version of the book chapter published in New Essays on Peirce’s Philosophy of Mathematics, Matthew E. Moore ed, Open Court, 2010.

https://www.academia.edu/25930950/Peirces_Topological_Concepts_Jerome_Havenel

A Category-Theoretic Reading of Peirce’s System: Pragmaticism, Continuity, and Existential Graphs.

Zalamea, Fernando. 2010.

In New Essays on Peirce’s Mathematical Philosophy, edited by Matthew E. Moore, pp. 203–233. Chicago: Open Court.

STEVIN NUMBERS AND REALITY

KARIN USADI KATZ AND MIKHAIL G. KATZ

2012

DISSERTATIONS ON PEIRCE

Indiana University

https://arisbe.sitehost.iu.edu/rsources/dissabs/diss.htm

The Continuum:
History, Mathematics, and Philosophy

by
Teppei Hayashi

A THESIS
DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY
GRADUATE PROGRAM IN PHILOSOPHY
UNIVERSITY OF CALGARY
CALGARY, ALBERTA December, 2017

New Essays on Peirce’s Mathematical Philosophy


Matthew E. Moore (ed.), New Essays on Peirce’s Mathematical Philosophy, Open Court, 2010, ISBN 9780812696813.

PEIRCE’S CONTINUUM

METHODOLOGICAL AND MATHEMATICAL APPROACH

FERNANDO ZALAMEA

“Modern Topology and Peirce’s Theory of the Continuum.” 

Johanson, Arnold.

Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 37, no. 1 (2001): 1–12. http://www.jstor.org/stable/40320822.

C. S. Peirce and the Nested Continua Model of Religious Interpretation

Slater, Gary

Oxford Theology and Religion Monographs (Oxford, 2015; online edn, Oxford Academic, 17 Dec. 2015), https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198753230.001.0001, accessed 2 Apr. 2023.

True Continuity and Analytical Continuity

In Continuity, discontinuity and negotiation of meaning in distributed virtual environments

Patrick John Coppock

https://arisbe.sitehost.iu.edu/menu/library/aboutcsp/coppock/Solomon/Solomon-True.html

C. S. Peirce and the Nested Continua Model of Religious Interpretation


Gary Slater, C. S. Peirce and the Nested Continua Model of Religious Interpretation, Oxford University Press, 2015, 242pp., $110.00 (hbk), ISBN 9780198753230.

Reviewed by Michael L. Raposa, Lehigh University
2016.06.07

Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews

Department of Philosophy
100 Malloy Hall
Notre Dame, IN 46556 USA
ndpr@nd.edu

https://ndpr.nd.edu/reviews/c-s-peirce-and-the-nested-continua-model-of-religious-interpretation/

On the relations between Georg Cantor and Richard Dedekind.

Ferreirós, J. (1993). 

Historia Mathematica, 20, 343-363.

“The mathematical continuum: A haunting problematic,”

de Freitas, Liz (2018)

The Mathematics Enthusiast: Vol. 15 : No. 1 , Article 9.
DOI: https://doi.org/10.54870/1551-3440.1421
Available at: https://scholarworks.umt.edu/tme/vol15/iss1/9

Continuity and infinitesimals.

Bell, J.L. (2013). 

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 

https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/continuity/

The continuous, the discrete and the infinitesimal in philosophy and mathematics.

John L. Bell

Switzerland: Springer, 2019, 313+xvii pp,

The Continuous and the Infinitesimal in Mathematics and Philosophy


John Lane Bell
Polimetrica s.a.s., 2005

The Continuum and the Evolution of the Concept of Real Number

John L. Bell

Department of Philosophy

The University of Western Ontario

jbell@uwo.ca

Varieties of Continua: From Regions to Points and Back.

Hellman, G, and S. Shapiro (2018). 

Oxford University Press.

The Continuous and the Discrete: Ancient Physical Theories from a Contemporary Perspective 

White, M. J. (1992). 

Clarendon Press, Oxford.

Varieties of Synechism: Peirce and James on Mind–World Continuity.

Calcaterra, Rosa M. (2011).

Journal of Speculative Philosophy 25 (4):412-424.

Review of Gary Slater, C. S. Pierce and the Nested Continua Model of Religious Interpretation

C. S. Peirce and the Nested Continua Model of Religious Interpretation. Gary Slater. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015. 242 pp.

Brandon Daniel-Hughes
John Abbott College

THE JOURNAL OF SCRIPTURAL REASONING

The Continuity of Continuity:
A Theme in Leibniz, Peirce and Quine

Begoña Ilarregui y Jaime Nubiola
Universidad de Navarra

Publicado en Leibniz und Europa, VI. Internationaler Leibniz-Kongress, 361-371.
Gottfried-Wilhelm-Leibniz-Gesellschaft e. V. Hannover., 1994.

https://www.unav.es/users/Articulo13.html

THE ABSOLUTE ARITHMETIC CONTINUUM AND THE UNIFICATION OF ALL NUMBERS GREAT AND SMALL

PHILIP EHRLICH

The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic

Volume 00, Number 0, XXX 0000

Click to access Ehrlich.pdf

DIVERGENT CONCEPTIONS OF THE CONTINUUM IN 19TH AND EARLY 20TH CENTURY MATHEMATICS AND PHILOSOPHY

JOHN L. BELL


Towards a classifification of continuity and on the emergence of generality

Daniel Rosiak
DePaul University, drosiak@depaul.edu

Department of Philosophy
College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences DePaul University
Chicago,IL

December, 2019

PEIRCE’S PLACE IN MATHEMATICS

BY JOSEPH W. DAUBEN

DEPARTMENT OF HISTORY, HERBERT H. LEHMAN COLLEGE, AND
Ph.D. PROGRAM IN HISTORY, THE GRADUATE CENTER,
THE CITY UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK, NEW YORK, NY 10036

HISTORIA MATHEMATICA 9 (1982) 311-325

CONTEMPORARY INFINITESIMALIST THEORIES OF CONTINUA AND THEIR LATE 19TH- AND EARLY 20TH-CENTURY FORERUNNERS

PHILIP EHRLICH

‘One, Two, Three:Fundamental Categories of Thought and Nature,

Charles Sanders Peirce

Three Infinitesimalist Theories of Continua

Philip Ehrlich

“The Absolute Arithmetic Continuum and its Peircean Counterpart”

P . Ehrlich,

in New Essays on Peirce’ s Mathematical Philosophy, edited by Matthew Moore, Open Court Press (forthcoming).

Charles S. Peirce’s Idea of Ultimate Reality and Meaning Related to Humanity’s Ultimate Future as seen through Scientific Inquiry

Noel E. Boulting, Mid-Kent College o fHigher and Further Education, Chatham, Kent, England

https://www.utpjournals.press/doi/pdf/10.3138/uram.16.1-2.9

THE SACRED DEPTHS OF NATURE
AN ONTOLOGY OF THE POSSIBLE IN THE PHILOSOPHY OF PEIRCE AND HEIDEGGER

Leon J. Niemoczynski
B.A., East Stroudsburg University, 2001 M.A., West Chester University, 2004

Department of Philosophy
in the Graduate School Southern Illinois University Carbondale May 2009

The Completeness of the Real Line

Matthew E. Moore

Department of Philosophy, Brooklyn College. E–mail: matthewm@brooklyn.cuny.edu

Crítica (Méx., D.F.) vol.39 no.117 Ciudad de México dic. 2007

“Logique et mathématique du Continu chez Charles Sanders Peirce”,

Havenel, Jérôme, 2006,

Doctoral Thesis, École des Hautes Études en Sciences Sociales, Paris.

https://www.theses.fr/2006EHES0079

A Less Simplistic Metaphysics: Peirce’s Layered Theory of Meaning as a Layered Theory of Being

Marc Champagne
Kwantlen Polytechnic University

December 2015

Sign Systems Studies 43(4):523-552
DOI:10.12697/SSS.2015.43A10

https://www.researchgate.net/publication/310446520_A_Less_Simplistic_Metaphysics_Peirce%27s_Layered_Theory_of_Meaning_as_a_Layered_Theory_of_Being

VIRTUAL LOGIC–THE COMBINATORIAL HIERARCHY: ‘ONE, TWO, THREE, INFINITY!’

Author: Kauffman, Louis
Source: Cybernetics & Human Knowing, Volume 19, Number 3, 2012, pp. 83-91(9)
Publisher: Imprint Academic

https://www.ingentaconnect.com/content/imp/chk/2012/00000019/00000003/art00006

6.3 ONE, TWO, THREE … ETERNITY

Subchapter in book

Cyber Semiotics: Why Information is not enough

Soren Brier

Peirce’s Prepunctual Continuum

MATTHEW MOORE

CUADERNOS DE SISTEMÁTICA PEIRCEANA
Número 7 – 2015
CENTRO DE SISTEMÁTICA PEIRCEANA
CSP

Time and the Continuum. An Introduction to the Problem(s)

Marcello Garibbo
University of Siegen

Philosophy Kitchen #13 — Anno 7 — Settembre 2020 — ISSN: 2385-1945 — Il Tempo e il Continuo.

Is Synechism Necessary?

Matthew Moore

Cognitio, Sao Paulo, Vol 14, No 1, 2013

Continuity of Space and Theories of Intersections

from Euclid to Leibniz

Vincenzo De Risi

Brouwer and Weyl: The Phenomenology and mathematics of the intuitive continumm

M Van Atten; D Van Dalen; R Tieszen

Infinitesimals and the continuum

John L. Bell

A formalization of forcing and the unprovability of the continumm Hypothesis

Jesse Michael Han; Floris Van Doorn

Peirce’s Conception of Metaphysics

Joshua David Black

Phd Thesis 2017

Peirce’s Triadic Logic : Continuity, Modality, and L

Odland, Brent C.

MS Thesis, 2020

University of Calgary

on the structure of continua

G T Whyburn

Potential infinity and intuitiontic Logic

Oystein Linnebo, Stewart Shapiro and Geoffrey Hellman

Conceptions of the continuum

Solomon Feferman

2009

the continuum east and west

Peter G Jones

Philosophy Pathways, 185, May 2014

https://philarchive.org/archive/JONTCE

Cauchey’s Continuum

Karin Katz and Mikhail Katz

Dicisigns: Peirce’s Semiotic Doctrine of Propositions

Synthese, Vol 192, No 4, 2015

Real Numbers, Generalizations of the Reals, and Theories of Continua

Time and the continuum

Lambalgen and Pinosio

Indefinite Divisibility

Jeffrey Sanford Russell

Inconsistent Boundaries

Zach Weber and AJ Cotnoir

Peirce’s mathematical logical approach to discrete collections and the premonition of Continuity

Helio Rebello

Cantor, Peirce and the True Continuum

Peirce and Cantor on Continuity

Stephen Gardner

https://www.academia.edu/3721816/Peirce_and_Cantor_on_Continuity

Charles Peirce on the Continuity of Thought

Dinh Huyen My

BS Thesis 2021

Charles University

william James psychology and ontology of continuity

Michela Bella

Toward a clarity of the extreme value theorem

Karin Katz

Mikhail Katz

Taras Kudryk

Time, Modality and three valued logic in Peirce and Lukasiewicz

Jose Renato Salatiel

Continuity and Mathematical Ontology in Aristotle

Keren Wilson Shatalov

The classical Continuum without points

Geoffrey Hellman and Stewart Shapiro

what is Categorical Structuralism?

Geoffrey Hellman

euclid’s geometry is just in our mind, rather than describing the real world

Arturo Tozzi

James Peters

The logic of Kant’s Temporal Continuum

Riccardo Pinosio

Varieties of Logic

Stewart Shapiro

Philosophical Aspects of Peirce’s Trivalent Logic

Jose Renato Salatiel

Philosophical problem of relations according to Peirce: Alliances towards an ontology of relations regarding two aspects of Synechism

Helio Rebello Cardoso Jr

Thein Spinelli Farraz

Are points (Necessarily) unextended?

Philip Ehrlich

C. S. Peirce and Aristotle on Time

Demetra Sfendoni-Mentzou

Applied Communicology in Org PR and R&D: Peirce on Synechism, Fuller on Synergetics, Gordon on Synectics, and Alinsky on Socialism

Richard Lanigan

The Continuity Debate: Dedekind, Cantor, Du Bois-Reymond, and Peirce on Continuity and Infinitesimals


Alison Walsh, Benjamin Lee Buckley
Docent Press, 2012

‘Hermann Weyl on intuition and the continuum’.

Bell, John L. (2000).

Philosophia Mathematica 8 (3):259-273.

Click to access Hermann%20Weyl.pdf

A Primer of Infinitesimal Analysis.

Bell, John L. (1998).

Cambridge University Press.

The Continuum: A Critical Examination of the Foundations of Analysis 

Weyl, Hermann, 

Dover (1987)

Brouwer and Weyl: The Phenomenology and Mathematics of the Intuitive Continuumt

M. Atten, D. Dalen, R. Tieszen
Published 1 April 2001

https://www.semanticscholar.org/paper/Brouwer-and-Weyl%3A-The-Phenomenology-and-Mathematics-Atten-Dalen/bde9d5572ce8952be18ff3abc9f6160be7d768d4

Hermann Weyl’s intuitionistic mathematics. 

D. van Dalen.

Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 1:145–169, 1995.

Mystic, geometer, and intuitionist. The life of L.E.J. Brouwer.

1: The dawning revolution.

D. van Dalen. 

Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1999.

The Continuity of Being: C.S. Peirce’s Philosophy of Synechism

by Brian Kemple

Epoché Philosophy Monthly

Issue #19 January 2019

https://epochemagazine.org/19/the-continuity-of-being-c-s-peirces-philosophy-of-synechism/

The Continuity of Peirce’s Thought

by Kelly A. Parker

Book 1998

The Concept of Continuity in Charles Peirce’s Synechism.

Benedict, George Allen (1973).

Dissertation, State University of New York at Buffalo

Peirce’s topical theory of continuity

Authors: Matthew E. Moore

April 2013 Synthese 192(4)

DOI:10.1007/s11229-013-0337-6

https://www.researchgate.net/publication/272036759_Peirce%27s_topical_theory_of_continuity

“Peirce’s logic of continuity: Existential graphs and non-Cantorian continuum.” 

Fernando Zalamea. 

Rev. Mod. Log. 9 (1-2) 115 – 162, November 2001 – November 2003.

https://projecteuclid.org/journals/review-of-modern-logic/volume-9/issue-1-2/Peirces-logic-of-continuity–Existential-graphs-and-non-Cantorian/rml/1081173838.full

Peirce’s Logic of Continuity: A Conceptual and Mathematical Approach

Fernando Zalamea

Book 2012

ISBN/EAN13: 0983700494 / 9780983700494

One, two, three . . . continuity: C.S. Peirce and the nature of the continuum

Author: Robertson, R.
Source: Cybernetics & Human Knowing, Volume 8, Numbers 1-2, 1 January 2001, pp. 7-24(18)

https://www.ingentaconnect.com/content/imp/chk/2001/00000008/f0020001/74?crawler=true

Does Continuity Allow For Emergence?

An Emergentist Reading Of Peirce’s Evolutionary Thought

Maria Regina Brioschi

https://doi.org/10.4000/ejpap.1647

https://journals.openedition.org/ejpap/1647

Peirce´s pragmatic meanings of mind and synechism

Lucia Santaella 
Full professor-Graduate program in Communication and Semiotics São Paulo Catholic University; member of the Advisory Board of the Peirce Edition Project 

lbraga@pucsp.br

https://www.pucsp.br/~lbraga/epap_peir4.htm

Feeling Our Way Forward: Continuity and Discontinuity Within the Cosmic Process, 

Joseph A. Bracken S.J. (2010) 

Theology and Science, 8:3, 319-331, DOI: 10.1080/14746700.2010.492625

Continuity and Inheritance: Kant’s Critique of Judgment and the Work of C.S. Peirce

John Kaag

Varieties of Synechism: Peirce and James on Mind–World Continuity. 

Rosa M. Calcaterra;

The Journal of Speculative Philosophy 1 October 2011; 25 (4): 412–424. doi: https://doi.org/10.5325/jspecphil.25.4.0412

Peirce’s Philosophical Perspectives. 

8 Peirce on Continuity

Potter, Vincent G. 

New York: Fordham University Press, 2019., doi:10.1353/book.67375.

https://muse.jhu.edu/pub/93/oa_monograph/chapter/2379541

Diagrams, Visual Imagination, and Continuity in Peirce’s Philosophy of Mathematics

by Vitaly Kiryushchenko

2023

THEORIES OF CONTINUITY AND INFINITESIMALS: FOUR PHILOSOPHERS OF THE NINETEENTH CENTURY

Lisa Keele

Doctor of Philosophy Thesis
in the Department of Philosophy,
Indiana University
May 2008

ProQuest Dissertations Publishing,  2008. 3319910.

TWO NEW GESTURES
ON PEIRCE’S CONTINUUM AND THE EXISTENTIAL GRAPHS

Fernando Zalamea (Universidad Nacional de Colombia)

77 Lebenswelt, 13 (2018)

Two New Gestures
on Peirce’s Continuum
and the Existential Graphs: Plurality of Pragmatic Imagination

Fernando Zalamea
Departamento de Matemáticas Universidad Nacional de Colombia

Associazione Pragma – 10th Anniversary Università degli Studi di Milano
October 18 2017

Click to access Milano(Ottobre2017).pdf

‘Logic of Relations and Diagrammatic Reasoning: Structuralist Elements in the Work of Charles Sanders Peirce’, 

Carter, Jessica, 

in Erich H. Reck, and Georg Schiemer (eds), The Prehistory of Mathematical Structuralism (New York, 2020; online edn, Oxford Academic, 18 June 2020), https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780190641221.003.0010, accessed 12 Apr. 2023.

https://academic.oup.com/book/41041/chapter/349349072

Peirce on continuity and his critique of Cantor and Dedekind.

Dauben, J. W. (1981).

In K. L. Ketner, J. M. Ransdell, C. Eisele, M. H. Fisch, and C. S. Hardwick (eds.), Graduate Studies Texas Tech University, pp. 93-98. Texas Tech Press.

The Peircean Continuum

Francisco Vargas

Matthew E. Moore

In book: The History of Continua (pp.328-346)

December 2020
DOI:10.1093/oso/9780198809647.003.0014

Advances in Peircean Mathematics

The Colombian School

Edited by: Fernando Zalamea
Volume 7 in the series Peirceana
https://doi.org/10.1515/9783110717631

https://www.degruyter.com/document/doi/10.1515/9783110717631/html

Charles Peirce and Modern Science

T L Short

Cambridge University Press
Online publication date: October 2022
Print publication year: 2022
Online ISBN: 9781009223508
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009223508

https://www.cambridge.org/core/books/charles-peirce-and-modern-science/A61CC6B9EBE0259AD8D83B2B85A82511

Peirce’s Theory of Signs

T L Short

Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Online publication date: July 2009
Print publication year: 2007
Online ISBN: 9780511498350
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511498350

The Practical Peirce: An Introduction to the Triadic Continuum Implemented as a Computer Data Structure

Author John Zuchero
Publisher iUniverse, 2007
ISBN 0595441122, 9780595441129

The Triadic Continuum is the invention of Jane Mazzagatti, a mathematician and software engineer. Mazzagatti came upon the idea for this new computer data structure, which is based on the work of Charles Peirce, while working on a project for Unisys Corporation. This same structure has proven commercially valuable in the efficient way it stores and allows for the analysis of large datasets. However, while learning about the nature of the structure she discovered more far-reaching implications to areas other than computer science. Charles Peirce was fascinated with how the mind reasons and with all of the scientific and philosophical implications of the mechanisms of how the brain records experience, constructs memories, and accesses previously stored experience and knowledge. Mazzagatti believes that she has rediscovered the structure of the Triadic Continuum, which is the foundation of many of Peirce’s key theories dealing with human reasoning and the logic of thought.
In this book the author, who worked with Mazzagatti writing patents for the invention, explains how this structure is unlike any other computer data structure or type of Artificial Intelligence-but more importantly why this structure may very well be a model for human cognition.